Stack Exchange Network

Stack Exchange network consists of 183 Q&A communities including Stack Overflow , the largest, most trusted online community for developers to learn, share their knowledge, and build their careers.

Q&A for work

Connect and share knowledge within a single location that is structured and easy to search.

What is the difference between idealism and materialism?

I understand what materialism is, but idealism - not so much. I know however they are opposing views, and would like to know what are the differences.

Analogies would be greatly appreciated.

  • metaphysics
  • materialism

Bar Akiva's user avatar

  • This is the question of what is fundamental. For materialism, the basic entities of reality are material and the mental is not fundamental. For idealism the converse is true. –  Quentin Ruyant Commented Feb 11, 2018 at 14:18
  • "I know however they are opposing views" - to be more precise, realism would be the opposite of idealism. –  Yechiam Weiss Commented Feb 11, 2018 at 15:36
  • @QuentinRuyant I still don't understand. Care to elaborate? Do you have an example? –  Bar Akiva Commented Feb 11, 2018 at 18:31
  • @YechiamWeiss and how is realism different than idealism? –  Bar Akiva Commented Feb 11, 2018 at 18:35
  • 1 @YechiamWeiss I don't think this is an accurate portrayal of Berkeley's view. First, Berkeley went to great lengths to argue that by whatever standard of reality you might have, his account delivers the result that there is a real world outside of you. Second, Berkeley denies that the real world is a 'projection' of your mind, in the way that hallucinations or dreams or imaginings might be projections. Rather, real objects depend for their existence on their being perceived, but dependence doesn't entail projection (whatever exactly that amounts to) –  possibleWorld Commented Feb 11, 2018 at 20:40

4 Answers 4

It's hard to give a once-and-for-all answer to this question, because what exactly materialism and idealism amount to depends largely on the historical era you have in mind.

That said, here's one way to cash out these notions. Materialism is the view that material objects exist. Idealism is the view that every object either is, or depends for its existence upon, mental entities.

Note that, as stated, these aren't opposing views, for it could be that material objects are either identical to or depend upon mental entities for their existence. (Edit: upon reflection I decided to redact the bit about Berkeley.)

However, anti-materialism sits pretty naturally with idealism, because if you deny that material objects exist you'll need some account of what objects are, and it looks like idealism offers a neat answer to that.

possibleWorld's user avatar

  • What if somebody believes mental entities (ideal objects) don't exist. I'm asking because your answer seems to imply ideal(ism) is primary. But what if materialism vs idealism is actually an opposition (two poles which cannot be conceived of separately) rather than two streams of thought? –  ttnphns Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 10:43
  • @ttnphns Sure, that's one way of characterizing out the positions. Like I said, the views I characterized aren't definitive, but are just one way you might go. –  possibleWorld Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 17:05
  • @ttnphns - I'd say you're on the right track. A third choice is implied. –  user20253 Commented Feb 22, 2018 at 11:44

I can offer only one angle on a many-sided question. I largely agree with the first answer. Then in my own terms :

This typically means that only ideas exist - ideas in the, or a, subject's mind. Hence Bishop Berkeley's claim that all that exist are minds or spirits and their ideas. Point to a so-called object in the external world, say a chair, and the answer from an idealist is likely to be that he chair is just a collection or complex of ideas : we say it is brown, but that means just that we have a perception of brown. We say that it is solid, but that only means that we will experience the idea - a feeling - of resistance if we touch it.

Berkeley needs careful handling. On his account ideas cannot be the effects produced in us by objects in the external world. Then how do they originate ? Among the minds or spirits is God. God produces in us all our ideas. What's more, God controls all minds or spirits simultaneously and creates the aggregates of ideas that we call chairs, the sun, and other constants and continuants in what we (or 'the vulgar') take to be the external world. Some ideas exhibit a regularity in our experience which causes us to regard them as Laws of Nature.

Though the term 'idealism' does not derive from Berkeley - Leibniz had already used it and Berkeley doesn't use it so far as I know - Berkeley's use of ideas as fundamental (along with the minds that have them) suggests the origin of the term in the notion of ideas. Idealism is idea-ism and only 'idealism' for ease of language.

▻ MATERIALISM

Various possibilities here but most, or quite, likely the view that all that exist are physical things. Everything that exists is purely physical and can be described in physical terms where the physical is whatever occupies a space/ time region.

This is an extreme form of materialism. Materialism can also refer to the view that them material has primacy, that it is fundamental and everything else dependent on or derivative from it. (Thanks to ttphns for reminding me of the distinction.)

This gives the broad contrast and I hope it helps.

Geoffrey Thomas's user avatar

  • I wouldn't generally equate phenomena with ideas (although it is ok in some specific traditions of thought). –  ttnphns Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 10:49
  • Materialism does not necessarily claim "everything is physical". It states material things are primary reality what exists, ideas - if there are - are secondary. –  ttnphns Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 10:53
  • I didn't say 'necessarily' : I qualified my definition with 'most, or quite, likely' the view that all that exist are physical things. And there are forms of materialism that do hold precisely this. –  Geoffrey Thomas ♦ Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 11:45
  • Left to myself I would not use the term, 'materialism', which is redolent of 19th-century philosophical controversies. I used the term only because the questioner had done so. –  Geoffrey Thomas ♦ Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 11:51
  • @ttnphns. You are perfectly right; I should have alerted the questioner to distinctions within materialism. I have now done so - with acknowledgement. Thank you. Please excuse my earlier abruptness. –  Geoffrey Thomas ♦ Commented Feb 12, 2018 at 11:59

I would like to add another aspect of the contrast between materialism and idealism. This addition is not entirely different from what previous answers have laid out but attempts to emphasize a different perspective perhaps.

Materialism claims that the material world is real and ideas reflect the material conditions that humans find themselves in. In particular, ideas are not freely floating in the aether but necessarily reflect the material reality of the world in one way or the other, either directly or indirectly. In other words, ideas are generalizations and/or approximations that we make to organize the understanding of the material conditions in which we find ourselves. Idealism is in direct contention with materialism most prominently on this last point. Idealism views ideals as primary and the material world as either just an instantiation of a complex set of ideas or as an approximation of the ideal world, e.g. the geometric objects in the real world were seen as an approximation to the ideal objects in the Platonic world.

Oftentimes, much of the content of the analysis done in either materialism or idealism can survive in idealism or materialism respectively. One just needs to turn it on its head as Marx famously said when he gave the materialistic version of Hegel's idealist dialectic analysis.

ACat's user avatar

Idealism is better than materialism because with out idealism we cannot get the science, idealism emphasis good character while materialism emphasis on the modern science and technology

Zainab Muhammad danmutuwa's user avatar

You must log in to answer this question.

Not the answer you're looking for browse other questions tagged metaphysics idealism materialism ..

  • Featured on Meta
  • User activation: Learnings and opportunities
  • Preventing unauthorized automated access to the network
  • 2024 Community Moderator Election Results
  • Should we change the text on our comment link?

Hot Network Questions

  • How is the universe able to run physics so smoothly?
  • Is there a faster way to find the positions of specific elements in a very large list?
  • Does legislation on transgender healthcare affect medical researchers?
  • Is it even possible to build a beacon to announce we exist?
  • cURL in bash script reads $HOME as /root/
  • In the absence of an agreement addressing the issue, is there any law giving a university copyright in an undergraduate student's class paper?
  • Could you compress chocolate such that it has the same density and shape as a real copper coin?
  • How to Vertically Stack Multiple Plots with Custom Color Functions and Opacity in Mathematica?
  • Is p→p a theorem in intuitionistic logic?
  • Is there any reason _not_ to add a flyback diode?
  • What is the simplest formula for calculating the circumference of a circle?
  • How do I avoid getting depressed after receiving edits?
  • How do I link a heading containing spaces in Markdown?
  • Day Convolution of Sheaves
  • Invalid date when setting one computer's clock from another
  • What exactly is a scratch file (starting with #)? Does it still work today?
  • How long has given package been deferred due to phasing?
  • Could you suffocate someone to death with a big enough standing wave?
  • Does a ball fit in a pipe if they are exactly the same diameter?
  • Can a floppy disk be wiped securely using the Windows format command with the passes-parameter?
  • God and Law of Identity Paradox
  • Is there a way to have my iPhone register my car which doesn't have carplay, only for the "Car is parked at"-feature?
  • How to map a list of elements to a list of positions of a matrix

materialism vs idealism essay

Materialism Vs. Idealism: A Comparative Study

Exploring the philosophical perspectives.

Idealism vs. Materialism

What's the difference.

Idealism and materialism are two contrasting philosophical perspectives that attempt to explain the nature of reality. Idealism posits that reality is fundamentally mental or spiritual in nature, emphasizing the primacy of ideas, consciousness, and the mind. According to idealism, the physical world is a product of our perceptions and thoughts. On the other hand, materialism asserts that reality is composed solely of matter and physical substances. Materialists argue that everything can be explained through the interactions of physical entities and that consciousness is a byproduct of the brain. While idealism emphasizes the importance of subjective experience and the power of the mind, materialism focuses on the objective and tangible aspects of the world.

Idealism

AttributeIdealismMaterialism
DefinitionBelief that reality is fundamentally mental or spiritual in natureBelief that reality is fundamentally physical or material in nature
Existence of GodMay or may not believe in a higher spiritual powerDoes not necessarily believe in the existence of a higher power
Source of KnowledgeRelies on intuition, introspection, and subjective experiencesRelies on empirical evidence, observation, and scientific methods
RealityPerceived as a product of the mind or consciousnessPerceived as a product of physical matter and interactions
ConsciousnessPrimary and fundamental, shaping realityEmerges from complex physical processes
Objective RealityMay argue that objective reality is subjective and dependent on perceptionBelieves in an objective reality independent of perception
Meaning and PurposeMay find meaning and purpose in spiritual or metaphysical realmsMay find meaning and purpose in physical experiences and achievements
AfterlifeMay believe in an afterlife or spiritual continuationDoes not necessarily believe in an afterlife or spiritual continuation

Materialism

Further Detail

Introduction.

Idealism and materialism are two contrasting philosophical perspectives that have shaped our understanding of the world and our place in it. While idealism emphasizes the primacy of ideas and consciousness, materialism focuses on the physical world and matter. In this article, we will explore the attributes of idealism and materialism, highlighting their key differences and similarities.

Foundations of Idealism

Idealism posits that reality is fundamentally mental or spiritual in nature. It asserts that ideas, thoughts, and consciousness are the primary constituents of the universe. According to idealists, the physical world is a manifestation or projection of the mind. Idealism places a strong emphasis on the power of human perception and the role of subjective experience in shaping our understanding of reality.

One of the key proponents of idealism is the German philosopher Immanuel Kant. Kant argued that our knowledge of the external world is constructed through our mental faculties, and that we can never truly know things as they are in themselves. Idealism also finds expression in various religious and spiritual traditions, which emphasize the importance of transcendent realities and the immaterial aspects of existence.

Characteristics of Idealism

1. Primacy of Ideas: Idealism asserts that ideas and concepts are more fundamental than physical objects. It suggests that the mind shapes and constructs the world we perceive.

2. Subjective Experience: Idealism places great importance on subjective experience and individual consciousness. It recognizes the diversity of human perspectives and acknowledges the role of perception in shaping our understanding of reality.

3. Transcendent Realities: Idealism often acknowledges the existence of transcendent or spiritual realms beyond the physical world. It suggests that there are deeper levels of reality that can only be accessed through introspection or spiritual practices.

4. Mind-Body Dualism: Idealism tends to view the mind and body as distinct entities. It suggests that the mind or consciousness is separate from the physical body and can exist independently.

5. Emphasis on Morality and Ethics: Idealism often places a strong emphasis on moral and ethical values. It suggests that the pursuit of truth, justice, and virtue is of utmost importance in leading a meaningful life.

Foundations of Materialism

Materialism, in contrast to idealism, asserts that the physical world and matter are the fundamental constituents of reality. It argues that everything, including consciousness and ideas, can ultimately be reduced to physical processes. Materialism emerged as a dominant philosophical perspective during the scientific revolution and the rise of modern science.

One of the influential figures in materialist philosophy is the French philosopher René Descartes. Descartes proposed a mechanistic view of the universe, suggesting that all natural phenomena can be explained in terms of physical laws and interactions.

Characteristics of Materialism

1. Primacy of Matter: Materialism asserts that matter is the primary substance of the universe. It suggests that everything, including consciousness and ideas, can be explained in terms of physical processes.

2. Objective Reality: Materialism emphasizes the existence of an objective reality that exists independently of human perception. It argues that the physical world can be studied and understood through empirical observation and scientific inquiry.

3. Reductionism: Materialism often adopts a reductionist approach, seeking to explain complex phenomena by breaking them down into simpler, more fundamental components. It aims to understand the whole by studying its constituent parts.

4. Mind-Body Monism: Materialism typically rejects the notion of mind-body dualism and argues for a monistic view of reality. It suggests that the mind is a product of physical processes in the brain and does not exist independently.

5. Scientific Methodology: Materialism aligns closely with the scientific method, valuing empirical evidence and rational inquiry. It seeks to explain natural phenomena through observable and measurable processes.

Comparing Idealism and Materialism

While idealism and materialism present contrasting views of reality, they also share some commonalities:

  • Both perspectives attempt to provide explanations for the nature of reality and our place in it.
  • Both recognize the importance of human perception and consciousness in shaping our understanding of the world.
  • Both have influenced various fields of study, including philosophy, psychology, and the natural sciences.
  • Both perspectives have their strengths and weaknesses, and neither can claim to provide a complete and comprehensive explanation of reality.

However, there are also significant differences between idealism and materialism:

  • Idealism places a greater emphasis on subjective experience and the power of human perception, while materialism focuses on objective reality and empirical evidence.
  • Idealism often acknowledges the existence of transcendent or spiritual realms, whereas materialism tends to reject such notions in favor of a purely physical explanation of the world.
  • Idealism tends to view the mind and body as separate entities, while materialism argues for a monistic view of reality where the mind is a product of physical processes.
  • Idealism places a strong emphasis on moral and ethical values, whereas materialism tends to prioritize scientific inquiry and the pursuit of knowledge.

Idealism and materialism represent two distinct philosophical perspectives that have shaped our understanding of reality. While idealism emphasizes the primacy of ideas and consciousness, materialism focuses on the physical world and matter. Both perspectives have their strengths and weaknesses, and they have influenced various fields of study. Understanding the attributes of idealism and materialism allows us to engage in meaningful debates and explore different ways of comprehending the world around us.

Comparisons may contain inaccurate information about people, places, or facts. Please report any issues.

Eras of Philosophy Logo

Materialism vs. Idealism:  Is the World What You Think?

Welcome! Today, we’re diving into a thought-provoking topic: materialism versus idealism. What are they, exactly? 

Materialism is the belief that physical matter is the fundamental substance in nature , and  all phenomena, including mental aspects and consciousness, are results of material interactions. On the  flip side , idealism posits that reality, or reality as we can know it, is fundamentally mental, spiritually constructed, or otherwise immaterial.

Why bother exploring these perspectives?  Well,  understanding these two  major  schools of thought enriches our grasp of philosophical debates that shape our worldview.  Whether we lean more toward the tangibles of science or the intangibles of consciousness, these ideas influence everything from our ethics to our politics.

So, let’s gear up for a journey into the core of philosophical differences, where every insight adds value to our understanding of the world. Ready to think deeply? Let’s go!

Table of Contents

The Origins of Materialism and Idealism

Historical development of materialism:.

Let’s kick things off with materialism. It all started with ancient thinkers like Democritus , who famously believed  that everything  is made up of tiny, indestructible units called atoms. Fast forward to the 19th century, and you meet Karl Marx , whose version of materialism—historical materialism—suggests that all societal structures stem from economic activity.  Simply  put, for materialists, everything that happens has a physical basis.

Historical Development of Idealism:

Now, onto idealism. This philosophy paints a different picture of reality. Plato , one of its earliest champions, introduced the idea of a world of forms or ideas that transcend the physical world. Fast forward to the 18th century, and we meet George Berkeley and Immanuel Kant, who argued that our perception shapes reality—what exists depends on our minds.  Idealism tells us  that  there’s more to the world than  just  atoms and  empty  space; our minds play a crucial role.

Understanding Both Sides:

Why does this matter? These contrasting views on the nature of reality have influenced countless aspects of human knowledge and society. Whether it’s the cold, hard facts of physics or the subjective experiences of the mind, grasping these concepts from materialism and idealism helps us navigate complex philosophical landscapes.

So, as we explore these rich histories and groundbreaking ideas, remember: the debates between materialism and idealism aren’t just academic—they’re about understanding the very fabric of existence. Isn’t that something to ponder over your next cup of coffee?

Core Principles and Theories

Key  principles of materialism:.

First  up , materialism champions a straightforward idea: the physical universe is all there is. Everything from your morning coffee to your thoughts about that coffee can be traced back to  physical  processes. But it gets deeper—materialists often embrace  determinism .  This  means every event, including human actions,  is the result of  preceding events governed by the laws of nature. Then, there’s  reductionism , the practice of analyzing and describing a complex phenomenon in terms of its simple or fundamental parts. Think of it like understanding a clock by examining each gear and spring.

Key  Principles of Idealism:

In the world of idealism, things  are not so cut  and dry.  Idealists argue that reality is shaped by our mental activities or even spiritually constructed.  This  doesn’t just mean our thoughts influence our reality —it means they   create  it.  Perception and consciousness aren’t just windows to the world; they are the architects of it. For idealists, diving into the mind’s role in crafting our environment is not just insightful—it’s essential.

Weighing Both Sides:

Understanding these principles isn’t just an intellectual exercise—it’s a way to broaden our perspectives. Materialism grounds us with its emphasis on observable and measurable phenomena, while idealism elevates our appreciation for the complexities of human consciousness and perception. What’s  more real : the physical brain or the mind it generates? As we dig into these philosophies, let’s keep our minds open to the profound implications each has on our understanding of the universe.

So, as we unpack these ideas, let’s enjoy the dance between  the  tangible and intangible aspects  of our existence .   Whether you lean towards the solid facts of materialism or the intricate ideas of idealism,  there’s  a whole world of thought waiting to be explored.  Who said philosophy couldn’t be as engaging as the latest drama series?

Materialism and Idealism in Modern Context

Application of materialism in science and technology:.

Materialism isn’t just an old philosophical relic; it’s alive and well in modern science and technology.  Take biology, for example, where genetic determinism suggests that our genes control  not only our physical traits but also  certain behaviors, predisposing us to various conditions.  Then there’s physics, where the materialist approach has us looking at the universe as a big, tangible machine where everything from stars to smartphones operates according to physical laws. This perspective is fundamental in developing technologies that transform our lives.

Application of Idealism in Ethics and Metaphysics:

On the flip side , idealism offers a refreshing lens, especially in ethics and metaphysics.  It prompts us to consider: What if reality is shaped by our beliefs and intentions?  This perspective can radically alter how we approach ethical questions. For instance, if our perceptions shape reality, how responsible are we for crafting a just world? In education, idealism inspires pedagogies that prioritize the development of the whole person, emphasizing critical thinking and self-awareness over rote memorization.

Navigating Both Worlds:

So, how do these ideas fit into our daily lives? Materialism helps us make sense of the world through data and hard facts, guiding technological advances that improve our physical existence. Meanwhile, idealism pushes us to question the  very  foundation of what we know and teach, encouraging a deeper reflection on our ethical and metaphysical assumptions.  Together, these philosophies offer a robust framework for understanding  not just  the world around us  but also  the potential of our place within it.

As we explore these applications,  keep in mind  that every scientific breakthrough and ethical dilemma reflects these deep-seated philosophical debates.  Whether you’re a tech enthusiast fascinated by the latest gadget or a deep thinker pondering  the big questions of life , these perspectives are more relevant than ever.  Let’s keep the conversation going—what new insights will the next breakthrough bring?

Comparative Analysis

Comparing Materialism and Idealism:

How do materialism and idealism interpret change and development in the universe? Materialism views change as a series of physical and deterministic processes, where everything follows natural laws like dominoes in a line. Idealism, however, suggests that change and development are influenced by human perception, ideas, and consciousness—essentially, our beliefs can shape the course of history.

The Nature of Human Existence and Free Will:

When it comes to  human existence and free will , the contrast sharpens .  Materialists argue that free will is an illusion, as our choices and actions  are the result of  chemical and physical processes. Idealists,  on the other hand , champion the idea that free will is real and significant, rooted in our ability to form ideas and make choices based on those ideas rather than mere physical stimuli.

Pros and Cons of Each Worldview:

Materialism:

  • Pros:  Offers a  clear , objective method to study the world, leading to advancements in science and technology.
  • Cons:  Can be seen as reductive, potentially overlooking the roles of consciousness and human experience.
  • Pros:  Emphasizes the importance of mental and ethical dimensions in shaping reality, enriching our understanding of human potential.
  • Cons:  Can be criticized for being too abstract and not sufficiently grounded in observable phenomena.

Limitations and Criticisms:

Materialism sometimes faces criticism for ignoring the subjective aspects of human experience, which are hard to explain through physical processes alone. Idealism, while uplifting, can be seen as impractical in its dismissal of the physical realities that we cannot simply wish away.

As we weigh these viewpoints, it becomes clear that both philosophies offer valuable insights but also come with their limitations. Whether you find yourself nodding along with the materialists or pondering with the idealists, understanding both sides enhances your ability to navigate and appreciate the complex tapestry of existence.

So, let’s keep this engaging dialogue open: which perspective resonates more with you, and why? Perhaps the answer isn’t just in the details but also in how we  choose to  view them.

Influence on Other Disciplines

Impact on politics and society:.

Materialism has made its mark on politics,  particularly  through Marxist theory. Marxism applies materialist philosophy to politics, arguing that economic factors primarily drive societal changes and class struggles.  This approach has  not only  shaped political policies and movements worldwide  but also  provided a framework for analyzing historical developments through the lens of material conditions.

Influence on Art and Literature:

Idealism has woven its threads deeply into the fabric of art and literature. Romanticism, for example, is steeped in idealist themes, celebrating emotion, individualism, and nature as a counter to the stark rationality of the Enlightenment. This movement encouraged artists and writers to explore and express the transcendent and sublime aspects of life that materialism often leaves untouched.

Influence on Religion and Spiritual Beliefs:

Idealism also plays a significant role in shaping religious and spiritual beliefs, emphasizing the importance of the spiritual and mental over the material. This philosophy supports the view that there is more to existence than what we can touch and see, encouraging a belief in a higher reality that shapes our physical world. From this perspective, our spiritual practices and beliefs are not just reactions to our environment but are integral to shaping it.

Weighing the Influence:

Both materialism and idealism profoundly impact various spheres of human activity. Materialism’s influence on political and scientific thought underscores its importance in practical and policy-making contexts, providing a solid ground for developing technologies and strategies that address material needs. On the other hand, idealism enriches our cultural and spiritual life, fostering a broader understanding of human experience and potential.

Whether  we’re  voting at the polls, marveling at a painting, or meditating in silence, these philosophies guide our actions and shape our worldviews. As we close this exploration, let’s appreciate how these deep-seated ideas continue to inspire and challenge us across all areas of life. Isn’t it fascinating how ancient thoughts still move modern worlds? Let’s keep this conversation going—how do you see these philosophies influencing your world?

Are you interested in learning about other philosophy types, such as Hedonism , Cynicism , or Epicureanism ? We have already covered those topics, so feel free to read them. Happy learning!

As we wrap up our exploration of materialism and idealism, we’ve delved into their origins,  key  principles, modern applications, comparative strengths and weaknesses, and their wide-ranging influence on disciplines like politics, art, and religion. We’ve seen how materialism emphasizes the tangible, guiding scientific and technological progress with its focus on physical reality. Idealism, in contrast, champions the power of the mind and spirit, influencing ethical thinking, artistic expression, and spiritual practices.

Now, I invite you to pause and reflect on your own beliefs. Which aspects of these philosophies resonate with you? Are you more inclined to see the world through the lens of material interactions or  through  the constructs of the mind?  Understanding your stance can enrich your perspective  not just on philosophy but on  life itself.

Looking ahead, the debate between materialism and idealism  is likely to  evolve with advancements in science, especially in fields like neuroscience and artificial intelligence, which challenge our understanding of consciousness and reality.  Likewise, societal shifts toward greater  awareness of  mental health and wellness may prompt a renewed interest in  idealistic  perspectives.

Let’s keep our minds open and our dialogues ongoing. What new insights will the future bring in the timeless dance between the material and the ideal?  Share  your thoughts, and let’s continue this fascinating conversation together. Isn’t it incredible how ancient philosophical debates still help us navigate the complexities of modern life?

RELATED POSTS

Cynicism

Cynicism: Friend or Foe? Unveiling the Hidden Truth!

Epicureanism

Epicureanism: Live Like a King Without the Palace!

Leave a comment cancel reply.

You must be logged in to post a comment.

  • Content Guidelines
  • Privacy Policy

Difference between Materialism and Idealism

materialism vs idealism essay

ADVERTISEMENTS:

This article will help you to differentiate between m aterialism and idealism.

The use of the term materialism demands that there is something called idealism and a comprehensive discussion of both is essential. Materialist philosophy emphasizes that its core idea is neither idea nor idealism, but rather it is physical world. It stresses upon the master or material condition of society and day-to-day life.

Materialism does not recognize anything beyond the physical world. In materialism or materialist philosophy there is no place of divinity or supernatural phenomena or elements or force. Man constitutes the nucleus of materialism.

Along with man, the society enters into the materialist philosophy. But there are many philosophers who deny this. They assert that only mind, thought, spirit and ideas are primary. Nature or the physical world is secondary.

The physical world is derived from spirit, consciousness and ideas. Man thinks something first and out of that imagination or thought physical world emerges. Physical world is a piece of man’s imagination.

Hence the difference between materialism and idealism may be succinctly stated in the following words:

“Those who consider that the material bases nature is primary and regard thought, spirit as a property of matter, belong to the camp of materialism. Those who maintain that thought, spirit and idea existed before nature and that nature is, one way or another, the creation of spirit and dependent upon it comprise the camp of idealism.”

From the early days of civilization a controversy has been going on between idealism and materialism. If we look at the development of history of philosophy we shall find that a major part of it is covered by the conflict between materialism and idealism.

But towards the middle of the nineteenth century Marx and Engels, through consistent and unassailable logic asserted that the matter or material world is real and idealism has no real basis, it is simply an imagination and, hence, it cannot be taken as the subject of any serious analysis.

Materialism or materialist philosophy is practically a protest against idealism or spiritualism. It is a guide to actual life and action. Materialism helps us to understand the nature, functioning and development of society. It does not proceed to ascertain happiness and pleasure of heavenly life.

It teaches man to be practical. It further states that the change and development of society are the results of human efforts and not dictated by the wills or whims of supernatural power.

Engels has said:

“Modern materialism is not a philosophy but a simple conception of the world (Weltanschauung) which has to establish its validity and be applied not in a science of sciences standing apart, but within the actual sciences.”

An important aspect of materialism or materialist interpretation of history is that man with his intellectual capacity can enter into the deepest stage of matter and can know what the matter is.

In other words, it is man’s intellectual capacity that helps to un-fathom the secrets of nature as well as matter, So we can say that man is the sole determiner of everything in the society.

Idealism asserts that it is not man nor his intellectual power nor his consciousness which determines the happenings of the physical world. The ideal or the eternal spirit determines the movements of the physical world.

As a result of this, idealism glorifies the death and also a life after death. According to philosophical idealism the external world is a misnomer. The only reality is the spirit or ideal.

The simple difference between the two is idealism forcefully says that ideal is all-in-all and naturally it determines everything. The opposite view has been propagated by materialism.

Materialism is, in its essence, an optimistic, life-asserting and radiant philosophy. It is alien to pessimism.

Materialism is the world outlook of progressive social groups and classes. The advocates of materialism always look ahead for a bright and enlightened future. It is imbued with optimism. The supporters of idealism generally argue that in materialism there is no place of morality, ethics and value judgment. But this charge against materialism is absolutely unfounded and moti­vated.

“In their dialectical and historical materialism Marx and Engels, far from rejecting progressive ideas, moral principles and lofty ideas, lay great emphasis on them.”

The distinction between materialism and idealism is not simply theoretical but also practical. The idealist philosophers have advised us not to rely too much on science. Science deals with logic and realities of the world. But the real truth lies beyond this real world.

The unseen world is more important and higher than the world in which we live. It guides men to lay their faith on superstitions and supernatural beliefs.

The church in the Middle Ages did this. The clergymen ingrained apathy in the mind of men towards the real world. The press and other media followed the line.

The idealists, through their continuous propaganda, assert that there are many things in the world which cannot be solved by science and technology. Only an inner and invisible power and regeneration of faith on the heavenly force can save mankind or emancipate man from sorrows and sufferings. The raison d’etre of this propaganda is quite manifest.

The capitalists know it very well that if the mind of the common people become too much materialist the real nature of capitalism would be exposed to them and that will stand in the way of capitalist exploitation.

Hence the best way is to divert the mind of people from the material world and help them to focus on the other-worldly affairs and idealism. Mainly for that reason there is an unholy alliance between capitalism and idealism. Marx and Engels challenged this and exposed the unholy alliance.

Related Articles:

  • Idealism, Materialism and Socialism
  • Essay on Views of Utilitarianism, Idealism and Democracy
  • Historical Materialism: Definition, Formulation and Principles
  • Essay on English Idealism

Upload and Share Your Article:

  • Description *
  • Your Name *
  • Your Email ID *
  • Upload Your File Drop files here or Select files Max. file size: 3 MB, Max. files: 5.

Politics , History , Difference , Materialism and Idealism

Upload Your Knowledge on Political science:

Privacy overview.

CookieDurationDescription
cookielawinfo-checkbox-analytics11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Analytics".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-functional11 monthsThe cookie is set by GDPR cookie consent to record the user consent for the cookies in the category "Functional".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-necessary11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookies is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Necessary".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-others11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Other.
cookielawinfo-checkbox-performance11 monthsThis cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Performance".
viewed_cookie_policy11 monthsThe cookie is set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin and is used to store whether or not user has consented to the use of cookies. It does not store any personal data.

English Studies

This website is dedicated to English Literature, Literary Criticism, Literary Theory, English Language and its teaching and learning.

Materialism in Literature & Literary Theory

Materialism, as a theoretical term, is a philosophical stance asserting that the physical world, composed of material substances, constitutes the fundamental and sole reality, thereby rejecting the existence of immaterial or supernatural entities.

Etymology of Materialism

Table of Contents

The term “materialism” finds its origins in ancient Greece, with its etymology stemming from the Latin word “materialis,” signifying a connection to matter.

Materialism is a philosophical doctrine that upholds the primacy of physical matter, contending that all phenomena, including mental and spiritual aspects, could be comprehended through the lens of material substances and their interactions.

This concept gained currency during the Enlightenment period in the 17th and 18th centuries and has since undergone various philosophical and scientific adaptations.

And it still continues to shape discussions regarding the nature of reality, the consciousness, and the interplay between the physical and non-physical dimensions of existence.

Meanings of Materialism

AspectMeanings
Philosophical MaterialismA worldview that posits physical matter as the fundamental reality and seeks to explain all phenomena in material terms.
A Marxist concept linking societal structure, economics, and ideology, often used to analyze literary works.
Consumer MaterialismPreoccupation with material possessions and their perceived role in happiness and status, often explored in literary characters.
Materialistic SocietyA culture valuing material wealth and possessions, influencing values and behaviors in literature.
Materialism vs. IdealismA literary theme contrasting materialistic pursuits with idealistic values, serving as a central tension.
Materialistic CharactersLiterary figures primarily driven by material gain, contrasting with characters emphasizing other values.
A literary approach examining how societal factors and power structures shape texts within their cultural and historical context.
Environmental MaterialismLiterary exploration of human-nature relationships, addressing ecological issues and consequences.
Critique of MaterialismLiterary works that critique materialistic values and their societal impact.
Materialism as a Literature emphasizing materialistic values as a central theme, prompting reflection on priorities and values.

Definition of Materialism as a Theoretical Term

Materialism, as a theoretical term , is a philosophical stance asserting that the physical world, composed of material substances, constitutes the fundamental and sole reality, thereby rejecting the existence of immaterial or supernatural entities.

It emphasizes the reduction of all phenomena, including consciousness and thought, to physical processes and interactions, underlining the importance of empirical observation and scientific inquiry in understanding the universe.

Materialism has historically played a significant role in shaping various philosophical, scientific, and sociopolitical discourses, often influencing interpretations of human existence and the natural world.

Materialism: Theorists, Works, and Arguments

  • Karl Marx developed the concept of historical materialism , which analyzes how economic structures influence society and culture, with significant implications for literary analysis.
  • Friedrich Engels , a collaborator with Marx, contributed to the development of historical materialism and its application to understanding society and literature.
  • Georg Lukács applied historical materialism to literature in his work The Theory of the Novel, exploring how economic and social conditions influence the novel as a literary form.
  • Raymond Williams introduced the concept of cultural materialism , which emphasizes the reciprocal relationship between culture and literature, highlighting their influence on each other.
  • In The Communist Manifesto (Marx and Engels), the authors outline key principles of historical materialism and discuss its profound implications for restructuring society.
  • Capital by Karl Marx provides a comprehensive economic analysis of capitalism, offering insights that have significantly influenced Marxist literary criticism.
  • The Theory of the Novel by Georg Lukács applies historical materialism to the analysis of the novel as a literary form, demonstrating how economic and social factors shape its development.
  • In Marxism and Literature by Raymond Williams, the author delves into the intricate relationship between Marxism and literature, introducing the concept of cultural materialism .
  • Historical materialism argues that economic and social structures are fundamental drivers of historical change, profoundly influencing the themes and representations found in literature.
  • Materialist perspectives frequently critique capitalist systems, as portrayed in “Capital,” for perpetuating materialistic values and exacerbating class disparities.
  • Materialism asserts that the material conditions of society, such as class struggle and economic factors, significantly shape literary works and their underlying themes.
  • Cultural materialism , as discussed in Marxism and Literature, posits that culture and literature are shaped by material conditions and social factors, offering a comprehensive approach to literary analysis that considers their interconnectedness.

Materialism and Literary Theories

– in Marxist theory, emphasizing socioeconomic and material conditions as the driving force behind literature.
– Literature reflects class struggle, economic disparities, and historical material realities.
– It provides a lens for analyzing class conflict, exploitation, and the impact of economic systems in literary works.
– to culture and language, considering culture and literature as products of material and historical circumstances.
– Relevant for examining how literature reflects and shapes cultural values, norms, and ideologies within specific historical contexts.
– Investigates how material conditions influence language and discourse in literary texts.
– to literary analysis, viewing literature as a product of material and historical conditions.
– Literature reflects societal changes and struggles related to class, economic structures, and power dynamics.
– in the context of environmental concerns, intersecting with materialism by considering the physical impact of human actions on the natural world.
– In eco-criticism, it allows analysis of how literature addresses ecological issues, resource exploitation, and the consequences of human material consumption.
– in feminist theory discussions of gender, economics, and power. – Examines how material conditions affect the lives of women and marginalized groups in literature. – Explores the intersections of gender and class within literary works.
– the impact of colonialism, imperialism, and globalization on societies and literature.
– In postcolonial theory, it is used for analyzing how literature reflects the material consequences of colonization, including economic exploitation and cultural transformation.

Materialism in Literary Criticism

  • Death of a Salesman by Arthur Miller: In this classic American drama, the character of Willy Loman epitomizes aspirations of the American Dream. Willy believes that success and happiness are directly tied to material wealth and professional success. However, his relentless pursuit of material success ultimately leads to his downfall, illustrating how a materialistic mindset can result in personal tragedy and disillusionment.
  • Madame Bovary by Gustave Flaubert: Flaubert’s novel follows the life of Emma Bovary, a woman who is dissatisfied with her provincial life and becomes obsessed with the pursuit of materialistic pleasures and social status. Emma’s materialistic desires lead her into financial ruin and a tragic end, serving as a critique of the emptiness of a life centered around material consumption.
  • American Psycho by Bret Easton Ellis: Ellis’s novel delves into the extreme materialism and consumerism of the 1980s Wall Street culture. The protagonist, Patrick Bateman, is a wealthy investment banker who obsessively indulges in material possessions, but he is also a psychopathic murderer. The novel explores the moral bankruptcy that can result from a society overly focused on material gain.
  • The Road by Cormac McCarthy : In this post-apocalyptic novel, materialism is juxtaposed with survival. The story follows a father and son as they navigate a harsh, desolate world where basic needs like food, shelter, and safety take precedence over material possessions. The novel underscores the fragility of materialism in the face of existential challenges.
  • The House of Mirth by Edith Wharton: Wharton’s novel examines the materialistic society of early 20th-century New York. The protagonist, Lily Bart, is a socialite whose life revolves around her quest for wealth and social status. Her relentless pursuit of material success ultimately leads to her downfall, highlighting the superficiality and cruelty of a materialistic society.

In these works, materialism is portrayed as a complex and often destructive force that can lead to moral decay, personal tragedy, and the erosion of human values. Each author critiques the materialistic values of their respective societies, emphasizing the need for a more meaningful and balanced approach to life beyond the pursuit of material wealth and possessions.

Suggested Readings

  • Eagleton, Terry. Marxism and Literary Criticism. Routledge, 2002.
  • Foster, Hal. The Art-Architecture Complex. Verso, 2013.
  • Jameson, Fredric. Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Duke University Press, 1991.
  • Leavis, F.R. The Great Tradition. New York University Press, 1960.
  • Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. The Communist Manifesto . Penguin Classics, 2002.
  • Moretti, Franco. Distant Reading. Verso, 2013.
  • Orwell, George. 1984 . Signet Classics, 1961.
  • Williams, Raymond. The Country and the City. Oxford University Press, 1975.
  • Wood, Ellen Meiksins. The Origin of Capitalism: A Longer View. Verso, 2002.
  • Zola, Émile. The Ladies’ Paradise (Au Bonheur des Dames). Penguin Classics, 2015.

Related posts:

  • Agency in Literary Theory
  • Differance in Literature & Literary Theory
  • Logocentrism in Literature & Literary Theory
  • Negritude in Literature & Literary Theory

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Home — Essay Samples — History — Communist Manifesto — A look at materialism and Idealism as illustrated by Marx in Comunist Manifesto

test_template

A Look at Materialism and Idealism as Illustrated by Marx in Comunist Manifesto

  • Categories: Communist Manifesto

About this sample

close

Words: 1168 |

Pages: 2.5 |

Published: Jun 29, 2018

Words: 1168 | Pages: 2.5 | 6 min read

Image of Dr. Charlotte Jacobson

Cite this Essay

To export a reference to this article please select a referencing style below:

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr. Heisenberg

Verified writer

  • Expert in: History

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays

Related topics.

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

materialism vs idealism essay

Class, Race and Corporate Power

Home > Arts & Sciences > Class, Race and Corporate Power > Vol. 6 (2018) > Iss. 2

The Significance and Shortcomings of Karl Marx

Chris Wright , Hunter College Follow

In this essay I explain both why Karl Marx remains an important thinker and why he is in some respects inadequate. I focus on the central issue of 'materialism vs. idealism,' and briefly explore ways in which contemporary intellectuals still haven't assimilated the insights of historical materialism. In the last section of the paper I examine the greatest weakness of Marxism, its theory of proletarian revolution, and propose an alternative conceptualization that both updates the theory for the twenty-first century and is more faithful to historical materialism than Marx's own conception was.

Creative Commons License

Recommended citation.

Wright, Chris (2018) "The Significance and Shortcomings of Karl Marx," Class, Race and Corporate Power : Vol. 6: Iss. 2, Article 3. DOI: 10.25148/CRCP.6.2.008310 Available at: https://digitalcommons.fiu.edu/classracecorporatepower/vol6/iss2/3

Since July 31, 2018

Included in

Political Science Commons

10.25148/CRCP.6.2.008310

  • Journal Home
  • About This Journal
  • Aims & Scope
  • Editorial Board
  • Submit Article
  • Most Popular Papers
  • Receive Email Notices or RSS

Advanced Search

ISSN: 2330-6297

Home | About | FAQ | My Account | Accessibility Statement

Privacy Copyright

PROCESS

  • Annotated Bibliography
  • Argumentative
  • Book Reviews
  • Case Studies
  • Communication and Media
  • Computer Technologies
  • Consideration
  • Environment
  • Explanation
  • Informative
  • Personal Experience
  • Research Proposals

Materialism vs Idealism

To get a clear picture of what materialism and idealism means, we can put a basic scenario in our everyday life, example the word "bed" we at once perceive a four legged structure with a mattress and beddings and through that perception, an image is created in our brain. But the question is if the things that caused the perception are real or not. Materialism would answer yes because not only can we perceive the existence of the object through our senses and grain but also through science and instruments which are worldly and separate from our minds. They claim the world consist of matter which undergoes constant change. Idealism would say No, because perception and awareness of the world entirely exist within our mind and can not be separated, hence nothing exists outside the mind. Idealist like Plato, Gottfried, George W., Argue that reality is somehow dependent upon the mind rather than independent of it. Materialism rejects the idea of absolute knowledge. Science can only improve knowledge but can not find ultimate or absolute truth. We gain knowledge by doing experiments, verify theories, explore the material world, but no knowledge can come from the world before exploring it.

Let’s find out together!

RATIONALISM VS EMPIRICISM

Rationalism focuses on the natural essence of the situation, what is truly witnessed by our senses. Rationalists claim that there are significant ways in which our concepts and knowledge are gained independently of sense of experience. Empiricism on the other hand claims that sense experience is the ultimate source of all our concepts and knowledge. Rationalist Descartes claims that what we know a priori is certain, beyond even the slightest doubt, while what we believe, or even know on the basis of sense experience is at least somewhat uncertain. However Empiricist Locke, Berkeley and Home, reject the thesis of intuition/ deduction saying that knowledge is a posteriori dependent upon sense experience. Reason alone does not give us any knowledge neither does it give us superior knowledge. It can be argued that we can be rationalist in mathematics and empiricist in physical sciences. Dealing with one subject, empiricist and rationalist will always conflict.

CONTRASTING THEORIES ABOUT THE MEANING OF LIFE

You can use our chat service now for more immediate answers. Contact us anytime to discuss the details of the order

There are two most common theories about life. There is the scientific theory where scientists believe that life evolved from simple organism that existed in the early earth to what it is today and still continues to evolve. Others claim that life began from outer space and then distributed among the planets example is Fred Hoyles. The other theory is bible based (Genesis 1), where there is a supreme being, God, who created the heavens and the earth (Descartes 114). The earth was without form, it was void, filled with darkness and the spirit of God move on the face of it. Life formed from His words, he spoke and it came to be. It is upon one's own belief on what life is and how it came to be. One may choose the scientific theory or the Biblical theory.

IS ABORTION EVER MORAL?

What is abortion? It is the termination of pregnancy by the removal or expulsion from the uterus of a fetus or embryo resulting in or caused by its death. It can either be spontaneous or induced. Abortion can be termed as moral give the circumstance or the cause of it. If it occurs because of complication so as to save the health of gravid (pregnant female) then it is viable. In a case where there is a miscarriage and the foetus has to be removed, then that also justifies the cause (Kenny 208). It can also be justified in case of rape of a young girl, who by all means can not carry the pregnancy to term due to undeveloped uterus, then in such a case, it should be allowed.

IS EUTHANASIA EVER MORAL?

Euthanasia is the act or practice of painlessly ending the life of someone suffering from an incurable illness. To measure the moral of something depends on ones beliefs and what is termed as acceptable to the society. Taking life of someone to remove them out of their misery is entirely on the people involved it is moral if the person gave the go ahead (Locke 212). God is the taker of life and it can be argued that when doctors try to preserve life of someone who is dying by putting machine to keep the hearts beating while in the real sense, the person would die, then they should let nature take its cause since it would happen anyway. It is the feeling of guilt that is created within us that we try our best to keep our loved ones alive but in the reality is, it is beyond us. In this regard it is proper to appreciate that man cannot make artificial life to last.

FREEDOM VS DETERMINISM

Freedom is being having power to exercise choice and make decisions without constraint from within or without while determinism is occurrence in nature that take place in accordance with natural laws. Freedom one can do what they want but can not go against nature. Example, one is free to fly, but nature does not allow one to, because we do not have what it takes to fly wings (Leinbiz 146). Imagine if we could all do everything that another can do? There would be chaos that is why nature wanted us to depend on each other.

Calculate the Price of Your Paper

Related essays

  • Philosophy: Epistemology and Ontology
  • Philosophy Final Exam Type
  • Machiavelli Influence

Along with the first order offer - 15% discount (with the code "MY15") , you save extra 10% since we provide 300 words/page instead of 275 words/page.

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

What is Materialism? What is Idealism

Profile image of Sajid Hussain

Related Papers

Kingsley L. Dennis

A short paper examining the negating influences of hyper-materialism; specifically through the lens of the philosophy of Rudolf Steiner.

materialism vs idealism essay

Antropología Experimental

Charles Wolfe

New materialism is not a clear-cut set of theses, or a firmly unified school of thought. It crosses discourses and theoretical commitments, but, as its name indicates, seems consistently to oppose ‘new’ materialism to an older form, or perhaps several older forms of this doctrine. The latter are typically associated with ‘mechanistic’ standpoints, with ‘reductionism’, with the denial of life, agency, embodiment, meaning, value … What happens when a historian of materialism confronts such claims? In what follows, I reflect on the historical problems which affect such theoretical positionings. It is not that there is no need to distinguish passive from active forms of materialism, or single out a focus on organic life. But that a distinction between ‘new and old’ might not be the way to capture such crucial theoretical and historical features.

Hiram Crespo

Crespo elaborates Epicurus' apolitical stance by arguing that the Epicurean canon, and particularly the organic, tangible pleasure/aversion faculty, should inform our ethical choices whereas ideologies like "free market neoliberalism" and "communist collectivism" have generated great human suffering, precisely because they divorced themselves from materialist hedonism. He also contrasts idealist and rationalist frequent lack of concern with the tangibles of ethics versus the paradigm of emergence which becomes evident when we study nature, arguing for organic, naturalist ethics instead of top-down ideals.

Journal of Marketing Management

Liselot Hudders , Mario Pandelaere , tina M lowrey , Ayalla Ruvio , Isabella Soscia

Philosophy Today

Iris van der Tuin

This is the introduction of the special issue 'New Concepts for Materialism.'

Seth A Biwul

A Hausa adage says, “Kudi da macigi abin kashewa” that is to say, as swift as one should kill a snake when he or she sees it, so also should money be spent as soon as it comes handy. Unfortunately, such spendings are almost always on self. This to a large extent is the worldview of the Nigerian (Christian), and such tendencies are reflected in their exotic dressing and hairdos, magnificent houses, big bank accounts, and latest model of cars among many others. While none of this in itself is bad, such a believer is observed to spend excessively on personal gratification, regardless of the needs of other societal members. This is a deviation from the biblical principle of moderation, brotherly love, care for the needy, and the believer’s responsibility to the community. This work of research was therefore carried out to explore the theologies that might have informed such materialistic tendencies within the Christendom and the philosophical foundations upon which such materialistic ideologies were built upon. Consequently, philosophies such as egoism, hedonism, humanism, and individualism were blamed for permeating the Christendom with such materialistic ideologies. Having gone through such explorations, the implications of a materialistic attitude on the believer, the society, Christian ethics, Christian theology, and missions were discussed. In a bid to proffer a solution, the writer propounded a theology of simplicity, generosity and contentment; care for the poor and needy within the church and society; and a theology of missions as suggested solutions for the materialistic believer.

Journal of Consumer Marketing

Aviv Shoham

Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Communication

Kathleen Feyh

Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 3.3 (2012), 281–292.

Andrew Melnyk

Materialism is nearly universally assumed by cognitive scientists. Intuitively, materialism says that a person’s mental states are nothing over and above his or her material states, while dualism denies this. Philosophers have introduced concepts (e.g., realization, supervenience) to assist in formulating the theses of materialism and dualism with more precision, and distinguished among importantly different versions of each view (e.g., eliminative materialism, substance dualism, emergentism). They have also clarified the logic of arguments that use empirical findings to support materialism. Finally, they have devised various objections to materialism, objections that therefore serve also as arguments for dualism. These objections typically center around two features of mental states that materialism has had trouble in accommodating. The first feature is intentionality, the property of representing, or being about, objects, properties, and states of affairs external to the mental states. The second feature is phenomenal consciousness, the property possessed by many mental states of there being something it is like for the subject of the mental state to be in that mental state.

Mike Haynes

Written for a blockbuster Encyclopaedia of Advertising and Business. Unfortunately it was pulled by publishers after this entry was completed and excepted. This paper reviews the debate on materialism and its role in western culture and I think still has some general value as a survey. Not to be confused with a survey of 'historical materialism'!.

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED PAPERS

Human Studies

Berel Dov Lerner

Jeff Poland

European advances in consumer research

Encyclopedia of Anthropology

Sebastian Job

Émilie Filion-Donato

Oxford University Online Encyclopedia

The Southern Journal of Philosophy

David Hiley

SSRN Electronic Journal

Journal of Economics and Behavioral Studies

Thomas Lemke

Journal of the Society for Psychical Research

Matt Colborn

Canadian Institute for Knowledge Development (CIKD)

International Journal of Organizational Leadership (IJOL)

Noga Arikha

The Journal of Philosophy

Rachel Haidu , Christoph Cox , André Rottmann

C Lalrindika Drtl Ls

M. Joseph Sirgy

Polish Psychological Bulletin

Malgorzata Górnik-Durose

Http Dx Doi Org 10 1080 0969725x 2014 920637

John Ó Maoilearca

Palgrave Macmillan US eBooks

Zvi Bekerman

Material Religion

Sonia Hazard

Andrew Clifton

Sahil Patni

Christopher Wright

Journal of Consumer Culture, 6 (2): 294 – 296

Nicolette Makovicky

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

To install StudyMoose App tap and then “Add to Home Screen”

Theories of Materialism and Idealism

Save to my list

Remove from my list

Prof. Finch

Theories of Materialism and Idealism. (2016, Aug 14). Retrieved from https://studymoose.com/theories-of-materialism-and-idealism-essay

"Theories of Materialism and Idealism." StudyMoose , 14 Aug 2016, https://studymoose.com/theories-of-materialism-and-idealism-essay

StudyMoose. (2016). Theories of Materialism and Idealism . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/theories-of-materialism-and-idealism-essay [Accessed: 18 Sep. 2024]

"Theories of Materialism and Idealism." StudyMoose, Aug 14, 2016. Accessed September 18, 2024. https://studymoose.com/theories-of-materialism-and-idealism-essay

"Theories of Materialism and Idealism," StudyMoose , 14-Aug-2016. [Online]. Available: https://studymoose.com/theories-of-materialism-and-idealism-essay. [Accessed: 18-Sep-2024]

StudyMoose. (2016). Theories of Materialism and Idealism . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/theories-of-materialism-and-idealism-essay [Accessed: 18-Sep-2024]

  • Differences Between Idealism and Realism Pages: 11 (3209 words)
  • Realism and Idealism in International Relations Pages: 4 (1060 words)
  • Comparing Idealism, Realism, and Marxism in International Relations Pages: 2 (515 words)
  • The Conceptions Of Idealism And Realism in Modern Science Fiction Pages: 6 (1778 words)
  • The Ideologies of Idealism and Realism in the 21st Century Pages: 3 (860 words)
  • Consequences of Romantic Idealism Pages: 6 (1614 words)
  • Idealism vs. Realism: Exploring Philosophical Perspectives Pages: 6 (1523 words)
  • Paco's youthful idealism in "For Whom The Bell Tolls": A symbol of lost innocence. Pages: 2 (570 words)
  • Chris McCandless: Idealism Unveiled Through Tragedy Pages: 3 (638 words)
  • Sherwood Anderson's Tale of Horse Racing Idealism Pages: 3 (759 words)

Theories of Materialism and Idealism essay

👋 Hi! I’m your smart assistant Amy!

Don’t know where to start? Type your requirements and I’ll connect you to an academic expert within 3 minutes.

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • Games & Quizzes
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction

Types distinguished by departures from the paradigm

Type distinguished by its view of history, types distinguished by their account of mind.

  • Greek and Roman materialism
  • Modern materialism
  • Translation central-state theories
  • Disappearance central-state theories
  • Eastern materialism
  • Reductionism, consciousness, and the brain
  • Logic, intentionality, and psychical research

Epicurus

  • Why is Denis Diderot significant?
  • What was Denis Diderot’s early life like?
  • How did Denis Diderot die?
  • Why is Thomas Hobbes important?
  • What was Thomas Hobbes’s childhood like?

United States Electoral College votes by state

materialism

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • Rebus Community Press - Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Mind - Materialism and Behaviorism
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Physicalism
  • Frontiers - The Not-So-Dark Side of Materialism: Can Public Versus Private Contexts Make
  • Humanities LibreTexts - Materialism and Behaviorism -- Introduction to Philosophy- Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy Now - What is Materialism?
  • Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Materialism
  • University of Missouri - Department of Philosophy - Materialism
  • The Basics of Philosophy - Materialism
  • materialism - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)
  • Table Of Contents

materialism , in philosophy, the view that all facts (including facts about the human mind and will and the course of human history) are causally dependent upon physical processes, or even reducible to them.

The word materialism has been used in modern times to refer to a family of metaphysical theories (i.e., theories of the nature of reality ) that can best be defined by saying that a theory tends to be called materialist if it is felt sufficiently to resemble a paradigmatic theory that will here be called mechanical materialism. This article covers the various types of materialism and the ways by which they are distinguished and traces the history of materialism from the Greeks and Romans to modern forms of materialism.

Types of materialist theory

Mechanical materialism is the theory that the world consists entirely of hard, massy material objects, which, though perhaps imperceptibly small, are otherwise like such things as stones. (A slight modification is to allow the void—or empty space—to exist also in its own right.) These objects interact in the sort of way that stones do: by impact and possibly also by gravitational attraction. The theory denies that immaterial or apparently immaterial things (such as minds ) exist or else explains them away as being material things or motions of material things.

In modern physics (if interpreted realistically), however, matter is conceived as made up of such things as electrons , protons , and mesons , which are very unlike the hard, massy, stonelike particles of mechanical materialism. In it the distinction between matter and energy has also broken down. It is therefore natural to extend the word materialist beyond the above paradigm case (of mechanical materialism) to cover anyone who bases his theory on whatever it is that physics asserts ultimately to exist. This sort may be called physicalistic materialism . Such a materialist allows the concept of material thing to be extended so as to include all of the elementary particles and other things that are postulated in fundamental physical theory—perhaps even continuous fields and points of space-time . Inasmuch as some cosmologists even try to define the elementary particles themselves in terms of the curvature of space-time, there is no reason why a philosophy based on such a geometricized cosmology should not be counted as materialist, provided that it does not give an independent existence to nonphysical things such as minds.

Still another departure from the paradigm is the theory that holds that everything is composed of material particles (or physical entities generally) but also holds that there are special laws applying to complexes of physical entities, such as living cells or brains , that are not reducible to the laws that apply to the fundamental physical entities. (To avoid inconsistency, such a theory may have to allow that the ordinary laws of physics do not wholly apply within such complex entities.) Such a theory, which could be called “emergent materialism,” can shade off, however, into theories that one would not wish to call materialist, such as hylozoism , which ascribes vital characteristics to all matter, and panpsychism , which attributes a mindlike character to all constituents of material things.

Another common relaxation of the paradigm is that which allows as compatible with materialism such a theory as epiphenomenalism , according to which sensations and thoughts do exist in addition to material processes but are nonetheless wholly dependent on material processes and without causal efficacy of their own. They are related to material things somewhat in the way that a thing’s shadow is related to the thing. A similar departure from the paradigm is a form of what might be called “double-aspect materialism,” according to which in inner experience one is acquainted with nonphysical properties of material processes, though these properties are not causally effective. A form of double-aspect theory in which these properties were allowed to be causally effective would be a species of emergent materialism.

materialism vs idealism essay

Of course, more than one of these qualifications might be made at the same time. If no other qualifications are intended, it is convenient to use the word extreme and to speak, for example, of “extreme physicalist materialism”—which is probably the type most discussed among professional philosophers in English-speaking countries.

In the wider world, however, the word materialism may bring to mind dialectical materialism , which was the orthodox philosophy of communist countries. This is most importantly a theory of how changes arise in human history , though a general metaphysical theory lies in the background. Dialectical materialists contrast their view with what they call “vulgar” materialism; and it does, indeed, appear that their theory is not an extreme materialism, whether mechanical or physicalist. They seem to hold merely that mental processes are dependent on or have evolved from material ones. Though they might be akin to emergent materialists, it is hard to be sure; their assertion that something new emerges at higher levels of organization might refer only to such things as that a computer is different from a mere heap of its components. And if so, even an extreme physicalistic materialist could acquiesce in this view. The distinctive features of dialectical materialism would thus seem to lie as much in its being dialectical as in its being materialist. Its dialectical side may be epitomized in three laws: (1) that of the transformation of quantity into quality , (2) that of the interpenetration of opposites, and (3) that of the negation of the negation. Nondialectical philosophers find it hard, however, to interpret these laws in a way that does not make them into either platitudes or falsehoods.

Perhaps because of the historical determinism implicit in dialectical materialism, and perhaps because of memories of the mechanical materialist theories of the 18th and 19th centuries, when physics was deterministic, it is popularly supposed that materialism and determinism must go together. This is not so. As indicated below, even some ancient materialists were indeterminists , and a modern physicalist materialism must be indeterministic because of the indeterminism that is built into modern physics. Modern physics does imply, however, that macroscopic bodies behave in a way that is effectively deterministic, and, because even a single neuron (nerve fibre) is a macroscopic object by quantum-mechanical standards, a physicalistic materialist may still regard the human brain as coming near to being a mechanism that behaves in a deterministic way.

A rather different way of classifying materialist theories, which to some extent cuts across the classifications already made, emerges when the theories are divided according to the way in which a materialist accounts for minds. A central-state materialist identifies mental processes with processes in the brain. An analytical behaviourist , on the other hand, argues that, in talking about the mind, one is not talking about an actual entity, whether material (e.g., the brain) or immaterial (e.g., the soul ); rather, one is somehow talking about the way in which people would behave in various circumstances. According to the analytical behaviourist, there is no more of a problem for the materialist in having to identify mind with something material than there is in identifying such an abstraction as the average plumber with some concrete entity. Analytical behaviourism differs from psychological behaviourism , which is merely a methodological program to base theories on behavioral evidence and to eschew introspective reports. The analytical behaviourist usually has a theory of introspective reports according to which they are what are sometimes called “avowals”: roughly, he contends that to say “I have a pain” is to engage in a verbal surrogate for a wince. Epistemic materialism is a theory that can be developed either in the direction of central-state materialism or in that of analytical behaviourism and that rests on the contention that the only statements that are intersubjectively testable are either observation reports about macroscopic physical objects or statements that imply such observation reports (or are otherwise logically related to them).

Before leaving this survey of the family of materialistic theories, a quite different sense of the word materialism should be noted in which it denotes not a metaphysical theory but an ethical attitude. A person is a materialist in this sense if he is interested mainly in sensuous pleasures and bodily comforts and hence in the material possessions that bring these about. A person might be a materialist in this ethical and pejorative sense without being a metaphysical materialist, and conversely. An extreme physicalistic materialist, for example, might prefer a Beethoven recording to a comfortable mattress for his bed; and a person who believes in immaterial spirits might opt for the mattress.

An outline of philosophy

2. Materialism versus idealism

Source: Victorian Labor College lecture, circa 1970 First published: Labor College Review , 1990-94 Transcription, mark-up: Steve Painter

From the earliest Greek philosophy, of which European philosophy is but a continuation, the philosopher has had to contend with the question: how is reality known? The answer is given from two principal viewpoints, the materialist and the idealist. The materialist method stands at one pole, the idealist at the other.

The distinctive features enabling us to recognise a materialist thinker can be summarised as follows:

1. The Basic proposition of materialism refers to the nature of reality regardless of the existence of humankind. It states that matter is first in order. When the earth was still a flaming sphere, resembling the sun today, before it cooled there was no life on its surface, no thinking creature of any kind. First we had matter incapable of thought, out of which developed thinking matter, humans.

2. The second aspect of materialism covers the relations between matter and mind. If what we have said above is the case — and we know it is from natural science — mind does not appear until we already have matter organised in a certain manner. The human brain, a part of the human organism, thinks. And the human organism is matter organised in a highly intricate form.

3. It is clear from the above why matter may exist without mind, while mind may not exist without matter. Matter existed before the appearance of any kind of mind on the earth’s surface. Matter existed before the appearance of a thinking human. In other words, matter exists objectively, independently of mind. Mind is a special property of matter organised in a special manner.

What are the distinctive features of idealism?

1. The basic element of reality to the idealist is mind, or spirit. Everything else comes from mind or spirit and depends upon its operation.

2. Mind or spirit exists before and apart from matter. Spirit is the abiding reality; matter no more than a passing phase, or illusion.

3. Mind or spirit is identical with, or emanates from, the divine, or at least leaves open the possibility of supernatural existence, power and interference.

4. From this it can be seen that idealism is a diluted form of the religious conception, according to which a divine mysterious power is placed above nature, the human consciousness being considered a tiny spark emanating from this divine power, and the human a creature chosen by god. The number of absurdities associated with idealism; such views as deny the external world, ie, the existence of things objectively, independent of the human consciousness, will be brought to the notice of students later in this course: it will be seen that the extreme and most consistent form of idealism leads to the height of absurdity in the so-called solipsism (Latin solus, alone, only; ipse, self). In a word, nothing exists outside myself, there is only my ego, my consciousness, my mental existence; there is no external world apart from me; it is simply a creature of my mind. For I am aware only of my internal life, from which I have no means of escaping.

Thus, it must be noted that the basic propositions of these two types of thought are absolutely opposed to each other. One must be right, the other wrong. Whoever maintains consistently the position of one is inescapably led to conclusions exactly contrary to the other.

Other points of view

We see that materialism and idealism are the two main tendencies in the field of philosophy, but there are other viewpoints also, combinations of ideas and methods that occupy a position between these extremes. For example, agnostics, who cannot decide whether an external reality actually exists apart from ourselves and whether it is possible to know it. They remain suspended between materialism and idealism.

In close association with the agnostics is the theory of knowledge devised by the German philosopher Kant. He taught that things in themselves existed as objective realities. This was in accord with materialism. But he then stated that humankind could never know them; all we could know were phenomena or things as they appeared to us. This placed Kant back among the idealists.

Many pragmatists refuse to take a firm stand on whether nature exists independently of human experience. They are not sure whether experience necessarily arises out of nature and after it, or whether nature emerges from experience. Although pragmatists claim to have overcome the opposition between materialist and idealist standpoints, they actually dodge the decisive issues between them in the theory of knowledge.

All these types of thinking are confused and inconsistent over fundamental problems. They usually end up in alignment with idealism.

The Milesian contributions to materialism

The Milesian school (about 585 BC) set aside religious attitudes and ideas, laying the foundations for materialist philosophy. The Iliad and The Odyssey , attributed to Homer, and completed about 550 BC held a place in Greek education and imagination comparable with that of the Bible in the Western world. In the opening scene of The Iliad , Homer tells how the Greeks camped before Troy for ten years, had been struck by a plague. Instead of searching for natural causes for this epidemic Homer attributed it to the anger of the gods for some unknown offence. The story goes that the Greek general, Agamemnon, had seized the daughter of a local caretaker of Apollo’s shrine. Apollo had answered the prayers of his priest for revenge by bringing the plague upon the camp. Acting upon this, the Greek generals forced Agamemnon to give up his concubine. This appeased Apollo, who lifted the plague.

The Milesians delivered a mortal blow to this mythological outlook by disposing of all gods. They went back to the beginning of all things and asked: what created the world and how was it done? These original materialists offered a coherent account, crude and inadequate as it was, of the creation of the world and of humankind without bringing in the gods or magical forces of any kind. The quality of this achievement can be gauged by noting that, during the same period, Judaism was emerging in Palestine, the religion of Zoroaster in Persia, Buddhism in India and Taoism and Confucianism in China. While countries were producing new religions the Milesians were breaking with the religious outlook altogether.

Origin of the laws of dialectics

The Milesians regarded the universe as composed of four major elements: earth, air, fire and mist. All the rest, the heavenly bodies, the world, plants, animals and humans, were in one way or another derived from the interactions of these elements. However, they offered no explanation of why things had to change or why they could not remain as they were. The first answers to this problem are found in the writings of an aristocrat, Heraclitus of Ephesus.

Heraclitus (500 BC) was designated by the German philosopher George Hegel (1770-1831) as the originator of the laws of dialectics. The old Greek philosophers, said Frederick Engels, were all natural-born dialecticians in their thinking. They looked upon phenomena as constantly changing and in perpetual motion, noted their interconnections, oppositions and contradictions as well as their transitions into something other than their original state. Heraclitus was the first theoretical analyst of the general process of change. He singled out fire as the first principle, the ultimate substance of things, from which all others were produced The following text from Heraclitus was preserved by Clement of Alexandria:

This world, which is the same for all things, was made by no god or man. It has always been, it is, and will be, an ever-living fire, kindling with measure and being quenched with measure.

An illustration of dialectical thought is his doctrine that everything flows. He gave picturesque examples of the universality of change. The sun is not only new every day but always continuously new. We cannot step twice into the same river, for its waters are ever-flowing, ever changing. All objects are and are not; they are never the same but always changing into something else. By this reasoning Heraclitus dissolved all fixed states of being into the process of perpetual becoming in which every object enters existence, stays for a while and then passes away.

He endeavoured to explain why not even the most stable and solid substances could remain unaltered or at rest. Everything is composed of opposites, he said, which are always in a state of tension. Any given form of matter is the result of the balance of opposing forces within it. This balance, however, is constantly being upset by the movement, the interaction, the contention of its warring opposites.

All things are involved in a dual movement; one emanates from the oscillations generated by the interactions of the opposites within itself; the other from the movement of the whole either toward or away from its source. And one of these antagonistic forces is gaining on the other all the time until in the end it proves triumphant.

Pairs of opposites must be considered as internally unified, Heraclitus taught. Disease makes health pleasant; hunger brings satisfaction. He cited the screw and its movement to illustrate this unity of opposition. The screw engages in two opposite forms of movement at one and the same time: straight and crooked. The spiral motion characteristic of its function has a contradictory nature; it goes both around and up, rotating on the same plane and on a different one at the same time.

The law of the identity or interpenetration of opposites as a primary feature of all things and as the explanation for their becoming and change we owe to Heraclitus. With its aid he was able to give a theoretical explanation of both the harmony and the disruption of things, of their intimate interconnection and transition from one into the other.

“The fairest harmony is born of things different, and discord is what produces all things.” Even the most harmonious and integrated unit cannot remain as such indefinitely because of the incessant movement of its opposites, the unbalancing of its contending inner forces. “Strife is the father of all things, the king of all things, and has made gods and men, free men and slaves.”

The vestiges of all beliefs to be found in the Milesian thinkers signify only that they could not go farther than the scientific knowledge and social framework of their epoch. It would have been unhistorical, unrealistic and unreasonable to have done more.

They stand at the entry of philosophic inquiry. It evolved something new, which went beyond the ideas of its predecessors and thereby promoted the progress of human thought.

The Atomists

The Atomists were the second outstanding school of materialist philosophy in Greece. They carried forward the Milesian investigations of nature and speculation about its processes. The real founders of this school were Leucippus (about 500 BC and Democritus about 460 BC). They conceived that matter is divided into small particles with empty space between them. They taught that everything consists of atoms and vacuum. Atoms are hard and have form and size; they are invisible, have no colour, taste or smell, since these are secondary or subjective properties, and they are in ceaseless motion.

Leucippus and Democritus postulated two kinds of ultimate existence. The full and the empty, the something and the nothing, the atom and the void. One was equivalent to being; the other to not being. Thus, they were in opposition to the Eleatic School (founded about 540 BC) which concluded that all things were essentially fixed and motionless and that change was an illusion of the senses.

Theophrastus, Aristotle’s successor as head of the Academy in Athens, wrote of Leucippus: “He assumed innumerable and ever-moving elements, namely, the atoms. And he made their forms infinite in number, since there is no reason why they should be one kind rather than another, and because he saw there was unceasing becoming and change in things. He held, further, that what is is no more real than what is not, and both are alike causes of the things that come into being: for he laid down that the substance of the atoms was compact and full, and he called them what is, while they moved in the void which he called what is not, but affirmed to be just as real as what is.”

By their specific union of what is with what is not, the Atomists reconciled the contradictory positions of Heraclitus that everything flowed and of the Eleatic School that nothing changed. The coupling of the atoms with the void explained both permanence and change, motion and rest, identity and difference. Neither changed in themselves but their incessant interactions gave rise to all the changes, combinations and differences of things in the universe.

It is important to note the Atomist conception of the world, for the void was no less essential to their theories than the atom. The notion of the void made motion theoretically explicable as well as sensibly apparent. The void in which the atoms moved and had their being was like nature, but it was completely featureless and wholly penetrable. The void was as passive and permeable as the atoms were restless and self-enclosed.

The Atomists had many incorrect notions about the universe. They believed that larger bodies fall faster in empty space than smaller ones. Another of their beliefs was that the fundamental physical elements were unchangeable and alike in substance. This has been disproved by modern science.

John Dalton’s experiments showed that the atoms of the elements were not alike; each had its characteristic weight. It was demonstrated in the 20th century that even the weight of atoms of the same elements is variable (isotopes). We now know that instead of being incapable of alteration and division, atoms are highly mutable, fissionable and fusionable. Moreover, atoms can act and react upon one another not simply by mechanical pressure and collision but also in electrical and other ways.

However, these developments do not invalidate the importance of the Atomists’ discoveries. They presented an accurate a picture of the inner constitution of the natural world and the modes of its operation and evolution as was possible with the available information, techniques and ideas.

In his book on the electron published in 1917, the American physicist and Nobel prize winner Milliken asserted: “These principles with a few modifications and omissions might almost pass muster today.”

Idealism of Plato and Aristotle

Most of the Atomists’ writings have been lost, but the scope of interests and investigations that inspired and supported these ideas can be judged from a list of their treatises compiled by scholars in Alexandria. Subjects covered include ethics; natural science (cosmology, astronomy, psychology and sense perception); logic (problems and criticisms of past theories); mathematics (geometry and numbers); music (rhythm and harmony, poetry and phraseology); technical works on medicine, agriculture, drawing and painting etc). Although they were more correct than their rivals and attracted allegiance from some of the finest minds, they were not a popular or dominant school of thought.

The reason for this is to be sought in the economics of the day. The idealist teachings of Plato (427 BC) and Aristotle (384 BC) reflected the conditions of the slave system. They were the ideological expression of the slaveholding aristocracy in its defensive battle for supremacy against the democratic tendencies emanating from the mercantile and plebeian forces in the Greek city-states. Idealism responded to the historical predicament in which the Greek propertied classes of money-lending landowners and slaveholders found themselves towards the close of the fifth century. For decades the Greek city-states had been racked by class dissension in which now the oligarchy and now democracy had the upper hand.

After imperialist expansion brought affluence and then disaster to the city, Athenian mercantile and maritime democracy came close to a dead end. It could neither help Athens regain its former greatness nor go further in changing its constitution because of the irremediable antagonism between the freeman and the slave. This period was the twilight of the first experiment in democratic government.

The idealists defended the oligarchic reaction against democratic forces. In his Dialogues , Plato takes up certain questions and lets discussion in an imaginary conversation play round them, showing their bearings and their implications, putting tentative solutions of them in the mouth of someone. There is no doubt that the Dialogues give us most of the leading ideas of his system of thought. Mystical craving was the deepest motive in Plato’s philosophy. He was driven to look for stable intellectual concepts by the need of the soul to find something stable on which it could rest in the midst of a world of change and passing away.

Plato felt a horror of change, especially concerning the desire to know. We could not really know things that were always changing and becoming something else, like the objects of our sensual experience. They slipped away in the midst of our attempt to grasp them. He sought to oppose change with geometry, in which we could acquire knowledge about the properties of figures that was absolutely stable, firm and quite independent of the imperfections of any figure we might draw. The circle of which geometry spoke, when it said such and such things were true of the circle, was not any such visible circle — for no visible circle was an absolutely perfect circle — it was the ideal circle. And yet the ideal circle did not belong to a world of merely human imagination. For the things that geometry said were true of the circle really were true, whether men apprehended them or not.

The word Plato applied to this perfect circle, which was not to be seen anywhere in our world, and to other similar entities was idea which meant shape or figure. But the word was also used in the sense of sort or kind. In this sense, the ideal circle stood for a whole class of things, circles. All the visible specimens of the class were imperfect approximations more or less to the class type, the perfect circle, which was unseen. If in geometry there was a possibility of stable knowledge in spite of the variability of things seen and handled, it seemed to Plato that, by laying hold of the idea, real knowledge in other fields could be gained in the same way. There must be an idea of men, to which all men in our world approximated more or less nearly. There must be an idea of justice to which our conception of justice approximated. Here we must understand the idea not only as existing in the mind but to mean for Plato that which had real existence apart from the human mind.

One of the major tasks of the idealists was to rehabilitate the religious outlook, which for many reasons had fallen into disrepute. It had been weakened by the clash of moral standards attending the civil war, and unsettled and old views of the universe along with the positions of the ruling classes. The growing disbelief in the ancient creeds and rituals had to be countered by the reinforcement of religion. The idealist philosophers undertook this by their own methods. For them was the special task of renovating religion for the educated aristocrats.

The idealist revisions of the nature of the gods arose from political calculations as much as from theoretical considerations. Religion was an indispensable instrument in the technique of aristocratic rule. The value of religion as social cement and an instrument of class domination was clearly recognised, candidly discussed and openly acknowledged by the idealists. Plato coupled with his immortality of the soul that according as men lived righteously or unrighteously, purely or sensually, they would be happy or miserable in the world beyond death. He opposed democracy, for him it meant the things he hated — agitation, disorder, noisy ignorance, indefinite variability. His ideal was a state remote from the demoralising influences of commerce, in which an established order worked generation after generation, in which the citizens were distributed in fixed classes and an aristocracy of the wisest ruled — all clear, clean and beautiful and restfully changeless.

In The Republic , Plato disclosed how conscious the Athenian oligarchs were of the usefulness of religious doctrines in maintaining class rule by advocating the “noble lie”. After having divided the inhabitants of his ideal state into the three categories of rulers, auxiliaries and producers, he discussed the means whereby this social hierarchy could be perpetuated and the decisions of the rulers enforced.

Plato asked: “How can we contrive one of those expedient falsehoods we were speaking of just now, one noble falsehood which we may persuade the whole community, including the rulers, themselves, if possible to accept?”

He answered that it would be best to present the formation of the class-divided society as an old Phoenician story; that is, invest its origins with an aura of antiquity to place it beyond immediate investigation and easy check-up. Then he goes on to say: “We shall tell them that all of you are brothers; but, when God was fashioning those of you who are fit to rule, he mixed in some gold, so these are the most valuable; and he put silver in the auxiliaries, and iron and bronze in the farmers and the craftsmen. Since you are all akin, your children will mostly be like their parents, but occasionally a golden parent may have a silver child or a silver parent a golden child, and so on; and therefore the first and foremost task that God has laid upon the rulers is, of all their functions as guardians, to pay the most careful attention to the mixture of metals in the souls of children, so that, if one of their own children is born with an alloy of iron or bronze, they must not give way to pity but cast it out among the craftsmen and farmers, thus assigning it to the station appropriate to its nature; and conversely, if one of these should produce a child with silver or gold in it, they must promote him to the guardians or auxiliaries, according to his value, in the belief that it has been foretold that, if ever the state should fall into the keeping of a bronze and iron guardian, it will be ruined. That is the story. Can you suggest any device by which we can get them to believe it?”

“Not the first generation, but perhaps their sons and descendants and eventually the whole posterity,” came the reply.

In this passage the connection between religious fables and the techniques of class domination is exposed to full view. To justify the caste system of Plato’s Republic , the citizens are to be duped into believing the noble lie that God created social distinctions. Plato was not the only one, then or since, to point out the political value of the noble lie in upholding social inequality.

Aristotle gave theology its name and regarded it as the highest of the sciences. In his system of ideas the divine is the immortal, the unchangeable, the ultimate source of motion, which is itself unmoved and unmovable.

In his book on metaphysics, Aristotle argues that there must be an eternal substance that causes eternal circular motion, and to be everlasting this substance must be immaterial. There must be something that moves the starry heavens without itself being moved. This unmoved mover is God, who directly sets the stars in motion by inspiring love and desire in their souls. All other things derive their movements from the same prime mover. This prime mover is knowledge that has only itself for its object. God’s sole activity is that of knowing.

Concerning astronomy and physics, Aristotle marks a step back from Plato, who had taught that the earth moved, and that it was not the centre of the universe. Aristotle had the earth once more unmoving at the centre of the universe. This scheme remained dominant, with certain modifications right up to the Middle Ages. Thus Aristotle’s false theories became the great hindrance to any advance in astronomical science until the days of Copernicus.

Christian theology plundered Plato and Aristotle and is deeply indebted to them. No small measure of their prestige and sustained influence as a philosophical tendency is due to their theological and teleological doctrines, which have proved to be enormously helpful to ideologists of the upper classes ever since.

3. Influence of Greek philosophy on Rome | Australian History Archive | 1. What is philosophy?

SEP logo

  • Table of Contents
  • New in this Archive
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

This entry discusses philosophical idealism as a movement chiefly in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, although anticipated by certain aspects of seventeenth century philosophy. It examines the relationship between epistemological idealism (the view that the contents of human knowledge are ineluctably determined by the structure of human thought) and ontological idealism (the view that epistemological idealism delivers truth because reality itself is a form of thought and human thought participates in it). After discussing precursors, the entry focuses on the eighteenth-century versions of idealism due to Berkeley, Hume, and Kant, the nineteenth-century movements of German idealism and subsequently British and American idealism, and then concludes with an examination of the attack upon idealism by Moore and Russell.

1. Introduction

2. idealism in early modern rationalism, 3. idealism in early modern british philosophy, 5. german idealism, 6. schopenhauer, 7. nietzsche, 8. british and american idealism, 9. the fate of idealism in the twentieth century, primary literature, selected secondary literature, other internet resources, related entries.

The terms “idealism” and “idealist” are by no means used only within philosophy; they are used in many everyday contexts as well. Optimists who believe that, in the long run, good will prevail are often called “idealists”. This is not because such people are thought to be devoted to a philosophical doctrine but because of their outlook on life generally; indeed, they may even be pitied, or perhaps envied, for displaying a naïve worldview and not being philosophically critical at all. Even within philosophy, the terms “idealism” and “idealist” are used in different ways, which often makes their meaning dependent on the context. However, independently of context one can distinguish between a descriptive (or classificatory) use of these terms and a polemical one, although sometimes these different uses occur together. Their descriptive use is best documented by paying attention to the large number of different “idealisms” that appear in philosophical textbooks and encyclopedias, ranging from metaphysical idealism through epistemological and aesthetic to moral or ethical idealism. Within these idealisms one can find further distinctions, such as those between subjective, objective and absolute idealism, and even more obscure characterizations such as speculative idealism and transcendental idealism. It is also remarkable that the term “idealism”, at least within philosophy, is often used in such a way that it gets its meaning through what is taken to be its opposite: as the meaningful use of the term “outside” depends on a contrast with something considered to be inside, so the meaning of the term “idealism” is often fixed by what is taken to be its opposite. Thus, an idealist is someone who is not a realist, not a materialist, not a dogmatist, not an empiricist, and so on. Given the fact that many also want to distinguish between realism, materialism, dogmatism, and empiricism, it is obvious that thinking of the meaning of “idealism” as determined by what it is meant to be opposed to leads to further complexity and gives rise to the impression that underlying such characterizations lies some polemical intent.

It nevertheless seems safe to say that within modern philosophy there have been two fundamental conceptions of idealism:

  • something mental (the mind, spirit, reason, will) is the ultimate foundation of all reality, or even exhaustive of reality, and
  • although the existence of something independent of the mind is conceded, everything that we can know about this mind-independent “reality” is held to be so permeated by the creative, formative, or constructive activities of the mind (of some kind or other) that all claims to knowledge must be considered, in some sense, to be a form of self-knowledge.

Idealism in sense (1) may be called “metaphysical” or “ontological idealism”, while idealism in sense (2) may be called “formal” or “epistemological idealism”. The modern paradigm of idealism in sense (1) might be considered to be George Berkeley’s “immaterialism”, according to which all that exists are ideas and the minds, less than divine or divine, that have them. (Berkeley himself did not use the term “idealism”.) The fountainhead for idealism in sense (2) might be the position that Immanuel Kant asserted (if not clearly in the first edition of his Critique of Pure Reason (1781) then in his Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783) and in the “Refutation of Idealism” in the second edition of the Critique ) according to which idealism does “not concern the existence of things”, but asserts only that our “modes of representation” of them, above all space and time, are not “determinations that belong to things in themselves” but features of our own minds. Kant called his position “transcendental” and “critical” idealism, and it has also been called “formal” idealism. In the interest of generality, we will call this sort of position “epistemological idealism”. Because of the many ways in which the term “metaphysical” is used—for example, Kant himself used the term “metaphysics” in two different senses, in one sense to refer to the derivation of knowledge from pure reason that he discredited but in another to refer to his own theory of the sources of knowledge, what we now call his epistemology—we will call idealism in sense (1) “ontological idealism”. If one accepts this characterization, then ontological idealism is meant to be opposed to both dualism, according to which reality ultimately consists not just of mental “stuff” but also of mind-independent matter, and to materialism, which takes matter to be all there is, while epistemological idealism is opposed to materialism but not necessarily to dualism. Epistemological idealism is sometimes motivated by the simple thought that whatever we know, we must know from our own perspective, but is sometimes motivated by further arguments. It does not automatically imply ontological idealism without further assumptions, although a commitment to ontological idealism obviously includes commitment to epistemological idealism since, assuming it allows for the possibility of knowledge at all, it allows nothing but the mental to be known. The further assumptions that lead from epistemological to ontological idealism can be a simple desire to avoid the possibility of doubt or ignorance by collapsing the distinction between knowledge and what is known, as when Berkeley claims that only his immaterialism can defend common sense, but can take other forms as well.

In what follows, we will concentrate mainly on the discussion of philosophical theories of idealism rather than the popular, everyday sense of the term. It is worth noting, however, that in its complex history—above all in the social as well as philosophical movement that dominated British and American universities in the second half of the nineteenth century and through the first World War—idealism in either of its philosophical forms was indeed connected to idealism in the popular sense of progressive and optimistic social thought.

The distinction between epistemological and ontological idealism that we are making here is hardly novel, although it was not made by many of the 17th- and 18th-century philosophers to be discussed below. The distinction was clearly formulated only in the 19th century. For example, the American philosopher Josiah Royce made this distinction at the end of the 19th century (albeit without our concern for the many possible meanings of “metaphysics”) when he called what we are terming ontological idealism “metaphysical” idealism. On his straightforward definitions, epistemological idealism

involves a theory of the nature of our human knowledge ; and various decidedly different theories are called by this name in view of one common feature, namely, the stress that they lay upon the ‘subjectivity’ of a larger or smaller portion of what pretends to be our knowledge of things

Metaphysical idealism, he says, “is a theory as to the nature of the real world , however we may come to know that nature”, namely, as he says quoting from another philosopher of the time, “‘the belief in a spiritual principle at the basis of the world, without the reduction of the physical world to a mere illusion’” (Royce, The Spirit of Modern Philosophy , pp. xii–xiii). Royce’s own view was that epistemological idealism ultimately works only on a foundation of metaphysical idealism, in particular that “the question as to how we ‘transcend’ the ‘subjective’ in our knowledge”, that is, the purely individual, although it exists for both metaphysical realists and idealists, can only be answered by metaphysical idealists (p. xiv). We will suggest, on the contrary, that while there are many good reasons for epistemological idealism, indeed, that—suitably broadly understood—it has in fact become the default epistemology of modern philosophy, many of the most important of modern idealists have sought to avoid any inference from epistemological to ontological idealism. This was particularly true in the 20th century, when tendencies toward epistemological idealism were in fact widespread in many schools of philosophy (although for different reasons than in the 18th century, reasons to be touched upon in the final section of this entry), very few philosophers were willing to identify themselves as idealists, even merely epistemological idealists.

As always when philosophy must decide between alternatives, there must be reasons or motives for deciding one way or the other. Since philosophical idealism in either of its forms does not seem to be the most obvious way in which to understand the nature of reality and the conditions under which its constitution can be known, it is of interest to look into the reasons and motives for idealism. Here one can distinguish between two major kinds of motives: those which are grounded in self-conceptions, i.e., in convictions about the role that the self or the human being plays in the world, and those based on what might correspondingly be called world-convictions, i.e., on conceptions about the way the world is constituted objectively or at least appears to be constituted to a human subject. Concerning motives based on self-conceptions of human beings, idealism has seemed hard to avoid by many who have taken freedom in one of its many guises (freedom of choice, freedom of the will, freedom as autonomy) to be an integral part of any conception of the self worth pursuing, because the belief in the reality of freedom often goes together with a commitment to some version of mental causation, and it is tempting to think that the easiest (or at least the most economical) way to account for mental causation consists in “mentalizing” or idealizing all of reality, thus leading to ontological idealism, or at least to maintain that the kind of causal determinism that seems to conflict with freedom is only one of our ways of representing the world, thus leading to epistemological idealism. Motives for idealism based on world-convictions can be found in many different attitudes towards objectivity. If one is to believe in science as the best and only way to get an objective (subject-independent) conception of reality, one might still turn to idealism, at least epistemological idealism, because of the conditions supposed to be necessary in order to make sense of the very concept of a law (of nature) or with the normativity of logical inferences for nature itself. If one believes in the non-conventional reality of normative facts one might also be drawn to idealism in order to account for their non-physical reality—Plato’s idealism, which asserts the reality of non-physical Ideas to explain the status of norms and then reduces all other reality to mere simulacra of the former might be considered a forerunner of ontological idealism motivated by concern for the reality of norms. An inclination toward idealism might even arise from considerations pertaining to the ontological status of aesthetic values (is beauty an objective attribute of objects?) or from the inability or the unwillingness to think of the constitution of social and cultural phenomena like society or religion in terms of physical theory. In short: There are about as many motives and reasons for endorsing idealism as there are different aspects of reality to be known or explained.

Although we have just referred to Plato, the term “idealism” became the name for a whole family of positions in philosophy only in the course of the 18th century. Even then, those whom critics called “idealists” did not identify themselves as such until the time of Kant, and no sooner did the label come into use than did those to whom it was applied or who used it themselves attempt to escape it or refine it. As already mentioned, Berkeley, the paradigmatic ontological idealist in the British tradition, did not use the name for his own position, and Leibniz, at least some versions of whose monadology might be considered idealist, also did not call his position by that name. Rather, in contrasting Epicurus with Plato, Leibniz called the latter an idealist and the former a materialist, because according to him idealists like Plato hold that “everything occurs in the soul as if there were no body” whereas on the materialism of Epicurus “everything occurs in the body as if there were no soul” (“Reply to the Thoughts on the System of Preestablished Harmony contained in the Second Edition of Mr. Bayle’s Critical Dictionary, Article Rorarius”, 1702, Philosophical Papers and Letters , p. 578), although in this text Leibniz also says that his own view combines both of these positions. It seems to have been Christian Wolff who first used “idealism” explicitly as a classificatory term. Wolff, often considered the most dedicated Leibnizian of his time (although in fact his position was more eclectic than at least some versions of Leibniz’s) set out to integrate the terms “idealism” and “materialism” into his taxonomy of philosophical attitudes of those “who strive towards the knowledge and philosophy of things” in the Preface to the other [second] Edition of his so-called German Metaphysics [ Vernünfftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt, den Liebhabern der Wahrheit mitgetheilet (Halle: Carl Hermann Hemmerde, 1747)]. Wolff distinguishes between two basic attitudes, one of which he sees exemplified by the skeptic, the other by what he calls “the dogmatist”. The skeptic doubts the possibility of knowledge in general and thus refuses to defend any positive claim at all. By contrast, the dogmatist puts forward positive doctrines, and these can be divided into those which posit as fundamental either one single kind of entities [ Art der Dinge ] or two different kinds. Wolff names the supporters of the first position “monists” and the adherents of the second “dualists”. This amounts to the division of all dogmatic doctrines, i.e., all knowledge-claims with respect to the ultimate constitution of reality, into monistic and dualistic theories. Here is where the term “idealist” then makes its appearance in Wolff’s typology: he distinguishes within the monists between idealists and materialists. Idealists “concede only spirits or else those things that do not consist of matter”, whereas materialists “do not accept anything in philosophy other than the corporeal and take spirits and souls to be a corporeal force”. Dualists, on the contrary, are happy “to accept both bodies and spirits as real and mutually independent things”. Wolff then goes on to distinguish within idealism between “egoism” and “pluralism”, depending on whether an idealist thinks just of himself as a real entity or whether he will allow for more than one (spiritual) entity; the first of these positions would also come to be called solipsism, so that solipsism would be a variety of (ontological) idealism but not all idealism would be solipsism.

Wolff’s way of classifying a philosophical system was enormously influential in eighteenth-century Continental philosophy—for example, it was closely followed by Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten in his 1739 Metaphysica , which was in turn used by Kant as the textbook for his metaphysics (and anthropology) lectures throughout his career, and whose definition of ontological (or “dogmatic”) idealism, as contrasted to his own “transcendental” or “critical” idealism, would also be that it is the position according to which there are only minds—and so it is no surprise that almost all talk about idealism was heavily influenced by Wolff’s characterization, at least as far ontological idealism was concerned. This is so because it reflects the main metaphysical disputes in seventeenth- and early eighteenth-century philosophy on the Continent quite well. In terms of Wolff’s distinctions, these disputes can be framed as disputes between (a) monists and dualists and (b) idealists and materialists; positions in this debate were often influenced by perplexities surrounding the (ontological) question of the interaction of substances, although they were also influenced by the (epistemological) debate over innatism. Although neither dualism, whose main representative was Descartes (who asserted the existence of both res cogitans and res extensa ), nor monism, allegedly represented paradigmatically by Spinoza in its materialistic version ( substantia, deus, natura ) and by Leibniz in its idealistic form (monad, entelechy, simple substance) succeeded in finding satisfying answers to this and related questions, in the early modern era these disputes shaped the conception of what the object of metaphysics ( metaphysica generalis sive ontologia ) was supposed to be.

Prior to Wolff, neither defending nor refuting (ontological) idealism seems to have been a central issue for rationalist philosophers, and none of them called themselves idealists. Yet what are by later lights idealistic tendencies can nevertheless be found among them.

While Descartes’s “first philosophy” clearly defends dualism, he takes his target to be skepticism rather than idealism, and thus is from our point of view concerned to resist epistemological idealism; Spinoza defends a form of materialism, but takes his primary target to be pluralism as contrasted to monism; and Leibniz does not seem overly worried about choosing between ontologically idealist and dualist forms of his “monadology”, while his famous thesis that each monad represents the entire universe from its own point of view might be taken to be a form of epistemological idealism, but Leibniz does not seem to conceive of it as such. Nicolas Malebranche’s theory of “seeing all things in God” might be the closest we find to an explicit assertion of both epistemological and ontological idealism in seventeenth-century rationalism, and thus as a forerunner of the “absolute” idealism of the nineteenth century. While from a later point of view it may seem surprising that these rationalists were not more concerned with explicitly asserting or refuting one or both versions of idealism, perhaps they were more concerned with theological puzzles about the nature and essence of God, metaphysical questions as to how to reconcile the respective conception of God with views about the interaction of substances of fundamentally different kinds, and epistemological problems as to the possibility of knowledge and cognitive certainty than they were worried about whether the ultimate constituents of reality were mental or material elements.

However, if one were to situate their thoughts within the framework provided by Wolff it is not that difficult to find traces of idealism (both ontological and epistemological) in their respective positions. With respect to their metaphysical or ontological teachings, this claim may seem surprising. Whereas according to Wolff (ontological) idealists are representatives of a species of metaphysical monism Descartes is one of the most outspoken metaphysical dualists. Hence to impute idealistic tendencies to Descartes’ metaphysics looks like a mistake. And in the case of Spinoza one could argue that though he definitely is a (very radical) monist and thus could count as an idealist within Wolff’s taxonomy, he normally is considered to be rather a materialist in Wolff’s sense. Consequently, it appears as if already for conceptual reasons there is no basis to burden either Descartes or Spinoza with traces of metaphysical idealism a la Wolff. Leibniz, meanwhile, often seems unwilling to commit himself to ontological idealism even though that is the most natural interpretation of his monadology, while only Malebranche, as noted, seems to come close to explicitly asserting epistemological and perhaps ontological idealism as well.

Nevertheless, both Descartes and Spinoza provide a starting point for their metaphysical doctrines with their conceptions of God, a starting point that is already infected with idealistic elements if (ontological) idealism is understood as implying a commitment to the primacy or at least the unavoidability and irreducibility of mental items in the constitution and order of things in general. Both agree that in order to gain insight into the constitution of the world one has to find out what God wants us, or maybe better: allows us to know about it (see e.g. Descartes: Meditations IV , 7–8 and especially 13; Spinoza: Ethics I , XVI). They also agree that the world is created by God although they have different views as to what this means. Whereas Descartes thinks of God as existing outside the world of the existing things He created (see Meditations III , 13 and 22) Spinoza holds that whatever exists is just a peculiar way in which God is present (see Ethics I , XXV, Corrolarium). Of all existing things all that God permits us to know clearly and distinctly is (again according to both Descartes and Spinoza) that their nature consists either in thinking or in extension. This claim can be seen as providing in the case of Descartes the basis for his justification of ontological dualism. His distinction between extended and thinking substances is not just meant to give rise to a complete classification of all existing things in virtue of their main attributes but also to highlight the irreducibility of mental (thinking) substances to physical or corporeal (extended) substances because of differences between their intrinsic natures (see e.g. Meditations VI , 19, and Principles of Philosophy I , 51–54). In the case of Spinoza thinking and extension not only refer to attributes of individual things but primarily to attributes of God (s. Ethics II , Proposition I, II, and VII, Scholium), making them the fundamental ways in which God himself expresses his nature in each individual thing. This move gives rise to his ontological monism because he can claim that all individual things are just modes in which God’s presence is expressed according to these attributes.

Although the idea that God is the creator of the world of individual existing things (Descartes) or that God himself is manifested in every individual existing thing (Spinoza) might already be considered to be sufficient as a motivating force for subsequent disputes as to the true nature of reality and thus might have given rise to what were then called “idealistic” positions in ontology, other peculiarities within Descartes’ and Spinoza’s position might well have led to the same result, i.e., to ontological idealism. Especially their disagreement about God’s corporeality might have been such a motive. Whereas Descartes denies vigorously the corporeality of God ( Principles of Philosophy I , 23) and hence could be seen as endorsing ontological idealism, Spinoza vehemently insists on God’s corporeality ( Ethics I , Proposition XV, Scholium) and thus could be taken to be in favor of ontological materialism.

Things are different when it comes to epistemological idealism. It seems to be very difficult to connect Descartes’ and Spinoza’s views concerning knowledge with conceptions according to which knowledge has something to do with a cognizing subject actively contributing to the constitution of the object of knowledge. This is so because both Descartes and Spinoza think of cognition as a result of a process in which we become aware of what really is the case independently of us both with respect to the nature of objects and with respect to their conceptual and material relations. Descartes and Spinoza take cognition to be a process of grasping clear and distinct ideas of what is the true character of existing things rather than a process of contributing to the formation of their nature. According to Descartes the sources of our knowledge of things are our abilities to have intuitions of the simple nature of things and to draw conclusions from these intuitions via deduction ( Rules for the Direction of the Mind III, 4 ff.). For him the cognitive procedure is a process of discovery (see Discourse on the Method , Part 6, 6) of what already is out there as the real nature of things created by God by finding out the clear and distinct ideas we can have of them ( Discourse , Part 4, 3 and 7). In a similar vein Spinoza thinks of knowledge as an activity that in its highest form as intuitive (or third genus of) cognition leads to an adequate insight into the essence of things ( Ethics II , Proposition XL, Scholium II, and Ethics V , Proposition XXV–XXVIII), an insight that gives rise to general concepts ( notiones communes ) on which ratiocinationes , i.e., the processes of inference and deduction, are based ( Ethics II , Proposition XL, Scholium I) whose results provide the second genus of cognition ( ratio ). Thus the problem for both Descartes and Spinoza is not so much that of the epistemological idealist, i.e. to uncover what we contribute through our cognitive faculties to our conception of an object, rather their problem is to determine how it comes that we very often have a distorted view of what there is and are accordingly led to misguided beliefs and errors. Given what they take to be a basic fact that God has endowed us with the capacity to know the truth (albeit within certain limits), i.e., to know to a certain degree how or what things really are, this interest in the possibility of error makes perfectly good sense ( Meditations IV , 3–17; Principles of Philosophy I , 70–72; Ethics II , Proposition 49, Scholium).

In his project for a “universal characteristic”, Leibniz can be regarded as having taken great interest in a method for inquiry, but he does not seem to have taken much interest in the epistemological issue of skepticism or the possibility of knowledge, and thus did not explicitly characterize his famous “monadology” as a form of epistemological idealism. But he did take a great interest in the ontology of substances, God the infinite substance and everything else as finite substances (in contrast to Spinoza, he rejected monism). Yet while the logic of his monadology clearly points toward ontological idealism, Leibniz frequently attempted to avoid this conclusion. One explicitly ontological argument for the monadology that Leibniz often deploys is that, on pain of infinite regress, everything composite must ultimately consist of simples, but that since space and time are infinitely divisible extended matter cannot be simple while thoughts, even with complex content, do not literally have parts, nor do the minds that have them, so minds, or monads, are the only candidates for the ultimate constituents of reality. Thus the late text entitled “The Monadology” begins with the assertions that “The monad which we are here to discuss is nothing but a simple substance which enters into compounds”, that “There must be simple substances, since there are compounds, [and] the compounded is but a collection or an aggregate of simples”, but that “where there are no parts, it is impossible to have either extension, or figure, or divisibility” and conversely where there is simplicity there cannot be extension or figure or divisibility (§§1–3). Yet monads must have some qualities in order to exist (§8) and to differ from one another, as they must (§9), and if the fundamental properties of matter are excluded, this leaves the fundamental properties of mind, which Leibniz holds to be perception, “The passing state which enfolds and represents a multitude in unity” (§14) and appetition, “the internal principle which brings about change or the passage from one perception to another” (§15; all from Philosophical Papers and Letters , pp. 643–4). This argument clearly seems to imply that all finite substances are ultimately mental in nature (and the infinite substance, God, is obviously mental in nature), so it seems as if Leibniz ought to unabashedly affirm ontological idealism, from which epistemological idealism would automatically follow, since if there is knowledge of reality at all, which Leibniz hardly seems to doubt, and reality is ultimately mental, then knowledge too must be of the mental.

Yet Leibniz often seems to avert such a conclusion by appeal to his idea of “preestablished harmony”, and this is possible because he himself interprets this idea in two different ways. Early in his career, in such texts as “Primary Truths” (1680–84) and the “Discourse on Metaphysics” (1686) (both texts unpublished in Leibniz’s lifetime and not known to his immediate successors such as Wolff and Baumgarten), Leibniz introduces the doctrine of preestablished harmony on truth-theoretical grounds. His argument is that everything that is true of a substance is so because the predicate of a true proposition is contained in the complete concept of its subject and because that complete concept reflects the properties or “traces” in the substance that is that subject; that there are true propositions linking every substance in the world to every other, thus the complete concept of each substance must be a complete concept of the universe itself and each substance must bear within itself as properties traces of every other in the universe; and thus that each substance must reflect, or, as mental, represent the entire universe. Yet since (finite) substances are also defined as existing independently of one another (although not existing independently from the infinite substance, God), there is a question as to why each should truthfully represent all the others, which Leibniz answers by appeal to the idea of a preestablished harmony: although considered from the point of view of the concept of substance it does not seem necessary that every substance truly represent all the others, in his goodness, thus in his preference for a maximally harmonious world, God has nevertheless made it such that they do.

In this mood, Leibniz tends to explain the existence of body as an artifact of the fact that each monad represents the world from its own point of view: physical locations and the bodies that occupy them are just the way in which the difference in the points of view of the monads is represented by them, but have no deeper reality; or, as Leibniz often says, space, spatiality, and bodies are just phenomena bene fundata , i.e. “well-founded modes of our consideration” ( Philosophical Papers and Letters , p. 270).

However, sometimes Leibniz writes as if space and time are not merely the way in which the pre-established harmony among monads presents itself to (their) consciousness, but as if the mental and physical or extended are two separate realms, each evolving entirely in accordance with its own laws, but with a pre-established harmony between them creating the appearance of interaction. Perhaps Leibniz was genuinely undecided between two interpretations of the pre-established harmony and two conceptions of the reality of body, sometimes being a committed idealism and sometimes a dualist. (As we will see later, even among the most committed absolute idealists of the nineteenth century it is not always clear whether they are actually denying the existence of matter or only subordinating it to mind in one way or another).

Leibniz’s monadology could thus be seen as a forerunner of both epistemological and ontological idealism, and his conception of space and time as phenomena bene fundata was clearly a forerunner of Kant’s transcendental idealism. But as we have just seen, he did not himself unequivocally affirm idealism, and as we will shortly see subsequent Leibnizians such as Alexander Baumgarten argued for dualism and for a corresponding interpretation of pre-established harmony. Nicolas Malebranche was also a dualist, committed to the existence of both mind and body, and an occasionalist, who held that since causation is necessary connection and the only truly necessary connection is between God’s intentions and their effects, bodies cannot directly cause modifications of minds (or each other) but rather there can be a causal relation between body and mind only if God intends the mind to undergo a certain modification upon the occasion of a certain change in a body (hence the term “occasionalism”). His further doctrine that the mind sees all things in God, however, depends on his particular view of what modifications the mind undergoes in perception. He holds that sensations are literally modifications in the mind, but that they are highly indeterminate, or in later terminology lack determinate intentional objects, and that genuine understanding occurs only when and to the extent that the determinate ideas in the perfect intellect of God are disclosed to finite, human minds, to the extent that they are. Malebranche’s position can be considered a theological form of Platonism: Plato held that the true Ideas or Forms of things have a kind of perfection that neither ordinary objects nor representations of them in human minds do, and therefore must exist someplace else; Malebranche takes the obvious further step of supposing that perfect ideas can exist only in the perfect intellect of God. He then supposes that human thought is intelligible to the extent that these ideas are disclosed to it, on the occasion of various sensations themselves occasioned by God but not literally through those sensations. The crucial point is that genuine understanding consists in the apprehension of ideas, even though these are literally in the mind of God rather than of individual human beings, rather than of physical objects, even though the latter do exist. Malebranche had significant influence on both Berkeley and Hume, though neither the former and certainly not the latter accepted his position in its entirety. His position that knowledge consists in individual minds apprehending ideas in some greater mind would also be recreated by idealists as late as T.H. Green and Josiah Royce in the second half of the nineteenth century, as we will later see.

Before we turn to British or Anglophone versions of idealism, earlier or later, one last word about idealism within pre-Kantian rationalist philosophy is in order. As earlier mentioned, dualism rather than ontological idealism became the default position of the German successors to Leibniz, the so-called “Leibnizo-Wolffians” who dominated the teaching of philosophy in many German universities from the second or third decade of the eighteenth century until the time of Kant and in some cases even beyond, and they correspondingly opted for the interpretation of the pre-established harmony as a relation between minds and bodies rather than among minds or monads alone. It may also be noted that defending dualism by means of an explicit “refutation of idealism” became the norm among these philosophers. This may be seen in Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten’s Metaphysica of 1739, which would become Kant’s textbook for his lecture courses in metaphysics and “anthropology” (empirical psychology) until the very end of the eighteenth century. Baumgarten accepts that the ultimate constituents of the world must be simples, hence monads of some kind. But he does not suppose that monads are necessarily minds or intellects, hence a dualism of monads is at least possible. Idealism would be the position that there are only intellectual monads; he says that “An intellectual substance, i.e. a substance endowed with intellect, is a spirit (an intelligence, a person)….Whoever admits only spirits in this world is an idealist” ( Metaphysics , §402, pp. 175–6). Baumgarten follows Wolff in distinguishing between two possible forms of idealism, first egoism, which admits the existence of only one spirit, that of the person contemplating such a doctrine, and then idealism proper, which allows the existence of multiple spirits. But both are refuted by the same argument. This argument builds on a Leibnizian principle not hitherto mentioned, the principle of plenitude, or the principle that the perfection of the most perfect world, which is the one that God created, consists in the maximal variety of the universe compatible with its unity or coherence (e.g., “Monadology”, §58, Philosophical Papers and Letters , p. 648), which was in turn the basis of one of Leibniz’s arguments for the identity of indiscernibles. Baumgarten then argues simply that a universe that contains not only more substances but also more kinds of substances rather than fewer is a more perfect universe, and necessarily exists in preference to the other; and a universe that contains not only multiple minds rather than a single mind but also bodies in addition to minds is therefore a more perfect universe than either of the former would be, and is the kind that actually exists. In his words, “the egotistical world, such as an egoist posits, is not the most perfect. And even if there is only one non-intellectual monad possible in itself that is compossible with spirits in the world, whose perfection either subtracts nothing from the perfection of the spirits, or does not subtract from the perfection of the spirits so much as it adds to the perfection of the whole, then the idealistic world, such as is posited by the idealist, is not the most perfect” ( Metaphysics , §438, p. 183), and hence not the kind of world that exists. No one outside of the immediate sphere of Leibnizianism would ever again proffer such a refutation of idealism. But both Baumgarten’s recognition of idealism and his refutation of it in a university textbook make it clear that by the middle of the eighteenth century idealism had become a standard topic for philosophical discussion, a position it would retain for another century and a half or more.

The relation between ontological and epistemological idealism is complex. Ontological idealism can be argued for on its own, and bring epistemological idealism in its train. Epistemological idealism can be argued for independently of ontological assumptions but lead to ontological idealism, especially in the hope of avoiding skepticism. Or epistemological idealism can be the basis for rejecting any pretenses to ontology, including ontological idealism. The first option may have been characteristic of some rationalists, such as Leibniz in his more strictly idealist mood. Both of the latter two are found within early modern British philosophy. We find considerations pushing toward epistemological idealism in both Hobbes and Locke in spite of the avowed materialism of the first and dualism of the second, who therefore obviously did not call themselves idealists. Berkeley argues for epistemological idealism and then adds ontological idealism in order to avert skepticism, although he calls his position immaterialism rather than idealism. Hume, by contrast, although calling himself neither an immaterialist nor an idealist, nevertheless adopts arguments for epistemological idealism similar to some of Berkeley’s, but then uses that position as the basis for a critique of traditional metaphysical pretensions, including those to ontological idealism—while also being drawn to ontological idealism in resistance to what he regards as the natural tendency to dualism. Hume’s critical attitude toward metaphysics is subsequently taken up by Kant, although Kant famously asserts on practical grounds some of the very same metaphysical theses that he argues cannot be asserted on theoretical grounds.

The British philosophers were all hostile toward dogmatic metaphysics in Wolff’s sense, although until the time of Hume, who had some familiarity with Leibniz, the metaphysics with which they were familiar were those of Descartes, Aristotelian scholasticism, and Neo-Platonism, which had become domesticated in Britain through the work of the Cambridge Platonists in the second half of the seventeenth century. All of these movements fed into the general movement of rationalism, while the British philosophers, typically lumped together under the rubric of empiricism in spite of their own differences, all believed, albeit for different reasons, that the doctrines put forward by dogmatic metaphysicians rest on a totally unfounded conception of knowledge and cannot survive rational scrutiny (empiricists might themselves be considered critical rationalists). Thus the primary task of philosophy for these philosophers became that of providing a theory of knowledge based on an adequate assessment of the constitution of human nature, for they were interested in knowledge only as a human achievement. However, it is not human nature in general that is of interest in this context but the workings of those human powers or faculties that are responsible for our human ability to relate to the world in terms of knowledge-claims. (Thus Kant’s attempt to argue on practical grounds for metaphysical theses that could not be justified on theoretical grounds would be a major departure from the methods of the British empiricists.) These faculties were attributed by the British as well as their Continental opponents to what was called “the mind” ( mens , consciousness, Bewußtsein ), an attribution which resulted in moving the “operations of the mind” into the center of philosophical attention. Reflections on the conditions of the possibility of knowledge led Hobbes and Locke to what might be considered forms of epistemological idealism in spite of their ontological commitments to materialism or dualism respectively, while Berkeley concluded that their epistemological idealism would lead to a skepticism that could be avoided only by his own more radical ontological idealism. Hume’s position remains complex and for this reason controversial. His thesis that our beliefs in causation, external objects, and even the self are all founded on “custom” and imagination rather than “reason” may be considered a form of epistemological idealism, but while he sometimes seems to attempt to avoid commitment on ontological questions altogether, at other times, as in his argument that the existence of external objects in addition to our impressions is only a fiction, he seems to infer ontological idealism from his epistemological idealism. In spite of their differences, almost all British philosophers from Hobbes up to and including Hume insisted that the highest priority for philosophy is to give an analysis of the conditions and the origin of knowledge, while they gave not only somewhat different accounts of what these conditions consist in and how they contribute to a convincing story about the origin of knowledge but they also had to face quite interesting “metaphysical” consequences from their respective accounts.

This is easily confirmed by looking briefly at some of their main convictions concerning knowledge, starting with Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679). As Hobbes points out in the chapters Of Philosophy and Of Method in the first part ( Computation or Logic ) of the first section ( Concerning Body ) of his Elements of Philosophy (1655), knowledge is the result of the manipulation of sensory input based on the employment of logical rules of reasoning (ratiocination) in acts of what he calls “computation”. He describes the details of this process most succinctly in a short passage in chapter 6 of the first part ( Human Nature ) of his The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic (1640), his first major philosophical work. After distinguishing what he calls “sense, or knowledge original” from “knowledge … which we call science”, he goes on to “define” knowledge “to be evidence of truth, from some beginning or principle of sense” and formulates four principles that are constitutive of knowledge: “The first principle of knowledge therefore is that we have such and such conceptions; the second, that we have thus and thus named the things whereof they are conceptions; the third is, that we have joined those names in such manner, as to make true propositions; the fourth and last is, that we have joined those propositions in such manner as they be concluding”. The message is straightforward with respect to both the basis and the formation of knowledge: senses (sensations) are basic to our acquisition of knowledge in that they lead to conceptions (representations) to which we attach names (concepts) which we then put together into propositions which, if true, already constitute knowledge, and from which there arise further knowledge if we draw conclusions in an orderly way from them.

Though the account given by Hobbes of the origin and the formation of knowledge is rightly called empiricist because it traces all knowledge back to the senses or sensations and their non-sensory causes, i.e., to what he calls “things without us”, it is by no means directly committed to any sort of ontological idealism or dualism; on the contrary, Hobbes’s preferred ontological position is materialism. Nevertheless, his account may lead to an early form of epistemological idealism. This is so because although Hobbes makes no claims as to either the constitution and the reality of what causes sensations or to any specific contribution on the part of the subject of knowledge to what we take to be the “accidents or qualities” of objects, he states, again most explicitly in the part on Human Nature in The Elements of Law , (1) that there are causes of our sensations which by way of their motions give rise to what we sense as qualities, but (2) that these qualities only have the status of “seemings and apparitions”. In his own words: “The things that really are in the world without us, are those motions by which these seemings are caused” ( Elements of Law , Part I, chap. II, 10). While he is confident that there are external objects, and thus has no intention of affirming ontological idealism, nevertheless because in Hobbes’s opinion we could have conceptions of these seemings even if there were no objects around (ibid. chap. 1, 8) there is for him no basis on which to found any metaphysical claims to the real existence of an external world or any epistemological basis for claiming knowledge of the real constitution of a subject-independent world or its real existence. Thus, Hobbes’s position is best described as agnosticism when it comes to metaphysics forced on him by a form of epistemological idealism. This is nicely confirmed by a passage from part II ( The First Grounds of Philosophy ) where he declares: “Now things may be considered, that is, be brought into account, either as internal accidents of our mind, in which manner we consider them when the question is about some faculty of the mind; or as species of external things, not as really existing, but appearing only to exist, or to have a being without us [emphasis added]. And in this manner we are now to consider them” (chap. VII, 1).

In spite of a pre-reflective disposition toward dualism, an explicit argument for an agnostic attitude with respect to the ultimate constitution of reality, thus a form of epistemological idealism without any argument for ontological idealism, is also characteristic of John Locke (1632–1704). Already in The Epistle to the Reader of An Essay concerning Human Understanding (1690) he denounces rationalist metaphysics as a “Sanctuary of Vanity and Ignorance” and declares in the first book of his Essay right at the outset: “I shall not at present meddle with the physical consideration of the mind; or trouble myself to examine, wherein its essence consists, or by what motions of our spirits, or alterations of our bodies, we come to have any sensation by our organs, or any ideas in our understandings; and whether those ideas do in their formation, any, or all of them, depend on matter or no [emphasis added]: These are speculations, which, however curious and entertaining, I shall decline” (Book I, chap. I, 2; s. also Book II, chap. XXI, 73). Instead he restricts his investigation to the “purpose to enquire into the original, certainty, and extent of human knowledge” (ibid.). Such an investigation presupposes an acquaintance with our own minds, and thus according to Locke the most pressing task is to understand the mind or the understanding itself. And because for Locke the sole material the mind has the ability to process are ideas, the most pressing task if one wants to understand the possibility of knowledge is to give an account of “how he [the mind] comes by them [the ideas]” (Book II, chap. I, 1).There is no need to go into the details of Locke’s conception of how the mind gets ideas and what the understanding does with them in order to arrive at knowledge. Though his description of these processes differs in some interesting ways from the model Hobbes proposes, in the end both Hobbes and Locke share the view (1) that whatever we can know depends on our having ideas which must be somehow based in sensation, (2) that there must be some external cause (Hobbes) or some source of affection (Locke) which gives rise to sensory ideas, yet (3) ultimately we are ignorant about the real constitution of these causes and these sources. What we know is the content and structure of our own ideas (epistemological idealism), although we have no reason to deny the existence of external objects (thus to assert ontological idealism) and even assume that in some regards external objects resemble our ideas of them (in the case of primary qualities).

Obviously it is mainly point (3) that is of importance for the question of how much dualism or ontological idealism is involved in Locke’s version of the operations of the mind. Again, as in the case of Hobbes, it seems that Locke’s position is meant to be neutral against and compatible with all these alternatives and that he wishes to stay agnostic with respect to them. This is indicated especially well by his theory of substance and his remarks concerning the limits of knowledge. Substances, Locke famously holds, “are such combinations of simple Ideas, as are taken to represent distinct particular things subsisting by themselves” (II, XII, 6). If one analyzes our concept of a substance one “will find he has no other Idea of it at all, but only a Supposition of he knows not what support of such qualities, which are capable of producing simple Ideas in us” (II, XXIII, 2). The reasons for this supposition are two: (1) we cannot make sense of the concept of an unsupported quality or of ideas subsisting by themselves, (2) we know from experience that “a certain number of these simple Ideas go constantly together” or “exist together” (II, XXIII, 2 and 3). Though Locke thinks of these reasons as totally compelling, he sees quite well that they do not justify any claim as to what a substance or a thing really is, what its nature or constitution consists in. Thus he never gets tired of emphasizing that we only have a confused idea of substance (a claim also made by Leibniz about three-quarters of our knowledge, although he held that we have a clear concept of what substance is), and repeats quite often (at least three times in Book II, chap. XXIII alone) that “Whatever therefore be the secret, abstract nature of substance in general, all the ideas we have of particular distinct sorts of substances, are nothing but several combinations of simple ideas, co-existing in such, though unknown, cause of their union, as makes the whole subsist of itself” (II, XXIII, 6). He restricts this agnostic attitude not just to corporeal substances or bodies but extends it to spiritual substances or minds as well: “It is plain then, that the idea of corporeal substance in matter is as remote from our conceptions and apprehensions, as that of spiritual substance or spirit; and therefore from our not having any notion of the substance of spirit, we can no more conclude its non-existence, than we can for the same reason deny the existence of body; it being as rational to affirm there is no body, because we have no clear and distinct idea of the substance of matter, as to say there is no spirit, because we have no clear and distinct idea of the substance of a spirit” (II, XXIII, 5). This criticism of any metaphysical claims concerning the ultimate constitution of reality is accompanied by a more general warning against the overstepping of the natural limits of our cognitive faculties. According to Locke it is just a fact about human nature that there are limits to the powers of the understanding. These powers are meant to be bestowed to us by God to an extent sufficient for us to know “Whatever is necessary for the Conveniences of Life, and Information of Virtue” (I, I, 5; s. also II, XXIII, 12) but only to that extent. If therefore the nature and the constitution of substances both corporeal and spiritual are beyond our cognitive grasp then we should take this to be a hint that God has set limits to what we can know because he sees no reason for us to know everything. Even if the powers He endowed on us would be magnified infinitely we still would remain clueless as to what substances really are because we still would be stuck in a world of qualities (this is one way of reading II, XXIII, 12). Thus, in the end metaphysical knowledge of any kind is meant to be beyond our reach. This, however, is nothing we should be concerned about: “For, though the comprehension of our understandings comes exceeding short of the vast extent of things; yet we shall have cause enough to magnify the bountiful author of our being, for that proportion and degree of knowledge he has bestowed on us, so far above all the rest of the inhabitants of this our mansion” (I, I, 5). For Locke, epistemological idealism combined with ontological agnosticism is an expression of piety. Locke’s position may be regarded as a theological expression of the most fundamental motivation for epistemological idealism: no matter how much we know about objects and at what level of detail, we still know them only from our own, human point of view.

The agnosticism with respect to the ultimate constitution of substances and things or of the fundamentum in re of “the ideas thereof” characteristic of Hobbes and Locke is challenged forcefully by George Berkeley (1685–1753), for whom their agnosticism becomes a form of skepticism and even impiety. In his Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710) he raises doubts about whether an agnostic stance along the lines of Hobbes and Locke can be upheld consistently if one thinks about the origin and the properties of ideas the way they do. Although in his Treatise Berkeley does not mention Hobbes at all and addresses Locke not by his name but by formulas like “esteemed philosopher” and “learned author” ( Treatise , Introduction, 11) very few times, it is abundantly clear that he wants to confront especially Locke with an ugly alternative: either his conception of a substance or a thing has “no distinct meaning annexed to” it ( Treatise , I, 17) and is nonsense, or he has to endorse not just epistemological idealism but ontological idealism as well. In other words, Berkeley’s point is that Locke cannot afford to be agnostic with respect to the metaphysical status of substances and things if he wants us to think of ideas as the immediate objects of human knowledge.

Berkeley’s position is thus that ontological idealism must be accepted along with epistemological idealism. His arguments in favor of ontological idealism based on the acceptance of ideas as the objects of human knowledge are rather straightforward, turning on presuppositions which he at least considered uncontroversial. Although his taxonomy of the different kinds of ideas deviate in ways that are not of interest here from Locke’s classification, he agrees with Locke that ideas exist only “in the mind” ( Treatise, I, 2). He takes the mind to be a “perceiving, active being” which itself is not “any one of my ideas, but a thing entirely distinct from them, wherein they exist or, which is the same thing, whereby they are perceived” (ibid.). From these stipulations he derives his most fundamental and famous claim (1) that “the existence of an idea consists in being perceived” (ibid.) or that “their esse is percipi ” ( Treatise, I, 3) by the perceiving, active mind. Already here Berkeley has the means in place to cast into doubt the meaningfulness of the assumption that there might exist unperceived objects or things. This is due to his restriction of existence to what is perceivable or, even narrower, to what is perceived: If the only objects that exist for a mind—whether it is my own mind or the mind of other human beings or the divine mind—are ideas because there is nothing else that can exist for the mind, then the very concept of something that exists but is not for the mind or is unperceived is a contradiction in terms. Thus if, as Berkeley supposes Locke does, one thinks of things as consisting of collections of ideas, he asks how could one take a thing to be something other than ideas and nevertheless to exist? This question underlies Berkeley’s confidence in what is often referred to as his “master argument”, the argument that one cannot conceive of anything existing unconceived because in trying to do so one is still conceiving of the object ( Treatise, I, §23). This seems open to the obvious objection that he is confusing the content of a proposition (for example, “The earth may still exist after the extinction of all conscious life”) with the act of entertaining (“conceiving”) such a proposition, which of course cannot take place except in a conscious being; but if he is already committed to the thought that objects of knowledge are nothing but ideas, it is at least understandable that he should overlook this distinction.

The second conviction, also meant to be damaging to Locke’s view about substances, on which Berkeley rests his case in favor of idealism is the claim (2) that “an idea can be like nothing but an idea” ( Treatise, I, 8). Although this claim is initially put forward in the context of his well-known criticism of Locke’s primary-secondary-quality distinction, it is equally relevant for his denial that there are things “without the mind”. The reasoning on which this claim is based seems to be the following: For two items to stand in the relation of likeness they must have something in common. However, if an idea is mind-dependent and if ideas are all there is for the mind, then what is “without the mind” must be different in every respect from an idea. Thus a relation of likeness cannot obtain between ideas “in the mind” and things “without the mind”. Berkeley puts this point quite bluntly by appealing to observation: “If we look but ever so little into our thoughts, we shall find it impossible for us to conceive a likeness except only between our ideas. Again, I ask whether those supposed originals or external things, of which our ideas are the pictures or representations, be themselves perceivable or no? if they are, then they are ideas, and we have gained our point; but if you say they are not, I appeal to any one whether it be sense, to assert a colour is like something which is invisible; hard or soft, like something which is intangible; and so of the rest” ( Treatise, I, 8).

There is a third claim that is essential to both Berkeley’s criticism of Locke and the idealistic position he is going to adopt. This is the claim (3) that ideas are passive and causally inert, i.e., they can neither produce nor alter another idea ( Treatise, I, 25). This claim he also bases on observation: “whoever shall attend to his ideas, whether of sense or reflection, will not perceive in them any power or activity; there is therefore no such thing contained in them. A little attention will discover to us that the very being of an idea implies passiveness and inertness in it, insomuch that it is impossible for an idea to do any thing, or, strictly speaking, to be the cause of any thing” (ibid.). Again the primary function of this claim is to discredit a Lockean view according to which we have to think of the primary qualities of things—which are contents of the most fundamental ideas we have of them—as the causes of sensations or of sensory ideas. It is, however, also meant to support the untenability of the assumption that agnosticism with respect to the real existence of mind-independent things is a viable option for a believer in Locke’s model of how and by what means we acquire knowledge of objects.

Berkeley’s criticism of Locke’s theory concerning substances is not carried out for its own sake. On the contrary, it is meant to establish what Berkeley thinks to be the unavoidable metaphysical consequences of a position that takes ideas “in the mind” to be the only material for the operations of the mind in its acquisition of knowledge. These metaphysical consequences consist in a thoroughgoing idealism (a term, however, never used by Berkeley himself, who preferred to call his position “immaterialism”) with respect to the nature and constitution of things or substances. Berkeley’s way of establishing this result is open to many questions. However, the basic outline of his overall argument can be sketched thus: If existence is restricted to ideas (and minds) and if, what is undoubtedly the case, things or substances exist, then things or substances must be ideas (or minds) too. Now, as Locke has convincingly shown, we can have ideas of particular things or substances, e.g., gold and lead, humans and sheep, distinguished by our ideas of their various properties, but we have only a confused or obscure idea of substance in general, which we suppose to underlie whatever collection of ideas we take to be a thing or a substance of one kind or another. But if we cannot have any ideas of things or substances other than our ideas of their properties, which clearly exist in minds, then the only clear ideas of things that we have is as ideas, and in that case, if they do not seem to exist in our own individual, human minds, then things or substances must be ideas in some other non-human, i.e., divine mind. This divine mind cannot be itself an idea because it must be conceived as an active principle that can be the cause of ideas, a principle of which we can have no idea but only a “notion” ( Treatise, I, 26, 27). Therefore, the very fact that we take things or substances to be real commits us to the claim that things are ideal entities perceived by the mind of God. Ontological idealism, one could say, is the only tenable basis for a realistic stance for Berkeley, but it leads to a realism about minds, human and divine, rather than of what he always calls material substance. And if one is to accept his re-interpretation of causality as a purported relation between ideas in terms of his theory of marks and signs, in particular his theory that what we think of as ideas of objects are signs of (God’s plan for) future possible ideas for us (cf. Treatise, I, 65 f.), then one also has to agree to epistemological idealism. But again, for Berkeley epistemological idealism without ontological idealism, the theory that all that exists are minds and their ideas, would be a form of skepticism.

Up until the point at which he introduces the mind of God into his argument, all of Berkeley’s considerations in behalf of epistemological idealism might be thought of as expressions of the basic insight that we can only conceive of reality from our own point of view, which are then extended into ontological idealism in order to avoid the whiff of agnosticism or skepticism and supplemented with the existence of a divine mind in order to satisfy an ineliminable tendency to believe in the existence of something more than one’s own mind or even of human minds in general. We will later see that the tendency to preserve both the impulse to idealism and the conviction that there is something more than ordinary human minds by positing a more than human mind is characteristic of many versions of idealism until the end of its glory days at the beginning of the twentieth century. This tendency is decidedly absent from the philosophy of David Hume, however.

David Hume (1711–1776) learned a great deal from Berkeley, above all his empiricist epistemology, but for the most part he tried to avoid Berkeley’s outright commitment to ontological idealism. Hume’s view that our knowledge consists of our ideas, our recognition of “philosophical” relations among them, such as identity and difference, and our recognition of “natural” relations among them such as causation, which are established by imagination and custom, can be considered a form of epistemological idealism—causality, in particular, which Hume regards as the basis of all our knowledge of existence, is at the same time reduced to a way of feeling and thinking, in other words a state of mind. But depending on how he is read, Hume either accepts the skepticism about possible external objects that Berkeley tries to avoid with an ontological idealism that renders any external objects other than other human or divine minds impossible, or else holds that even if there are valid arguments for skepticism it is psychologically impossible for human beings to remain in a skeptical frame of mind, thus we naturally even if not rationally believe in the existence of objects apart from our ideas of them. However, in those passages, prominently in Book I, Part IV of his early Treatise of Human Nature (1739–40), where Hume entertains a kind of monism that sees both “minds” and “objects” as nothing but different sets or “bundles” of one sort of thing, namely, perceptions, impressions and their paler copies, ideas, his position might seem much like Berkeley’s ontological idealism, with the difference that while he reduces all reality to mental states like impressions and ideas he does not see these as properties that must inhere in substantial minds any more than in substantial bodies, both of which are fictions we introduce in order to explain continuities among those impressions or ideas (although it may be difficult to explain who is introducing those fictions without resorting to substantial minds after all).

Hume’s version of epistemological idealism with regard to causation is clearly on view in his 1748 Enquiry concerning Human Knowledge , which was quickly translated into German and would eventually provide Kant with the stimulus for his own aprioristic rather than empiricistic version of epistemological idealism with regard not only to causation but to all of what he called the categories of pure reason, including especially substance and interaction as well as causation. But since Kant was not familiar with the contents of Hume’s earlier Treatise of Human Nature , he did not know that Hume too had generalized his approach to causality to the cases of mind and body, nor did he know that Hume may have tried to sidestep Berkeley’s commitment to substances but not his ontological idealism altogether by his theory of both minds and bodies as bundles of perceptions. Kant would try to avert Berkeley’s ontological idealism by a different stratagem, but before we come to that we must consider Hume’s position more fully. Hume accepted from Locke and Descartes before him that the immediate objects of consciousness are what they had called ideas, although he reserves that word for copies or subsequently recalled perceptions rather than the originally experienced perceptions that he calls impressions. He also adopts the view of his predecessors that knowledge lies in the recognition of relations among impressions, ideas, or both, and divides those relations into two kinds, philosophical and natural. Philosophical relations are those immediately evident on reflection on or comparison of particular ideas, and include resemblance, identity, spatial and temporal relations such as above and below or before and after, number and degree, and logical contrariety ( Treatise of Human Nature , I.I.5), while natural relations are those that are not immediately evident on reflection on a single impression or idea or in a single comparison of any number, but which instead become evident, or more properly are formed, only through repeated experience. Hume’s best known argument is then that causation is not a philosophical but a natural relation: the causal relation is comprised by temporal succession, spatial contiguity, and necessary connection, and while the first two are philosophical relations that are immediately apparent, the necessary connection between different ideas—those of a cause and its separate effect—is, unlike the necessary identity of two qualitatively similar ideas, not immediately apparent, as Hume puts it, to reason (I.III.2), but instead grows only out of repeated experience, the repeated experience of qualitatively similar pairs of impressions which causes them to become linked in the mind, as we would ordinarily say, or at least in consciousness, as the careful Hume should say at most (I.III.6). In fact, Hume’s argument is that repeated experience itself has two effects: it creates a habit of thought such that upon the presentation of an impression of one kind that has repeatedly been experienced in spatial and temporal conjunction with one of another kind, a vivid version of the idea of the kind of impression with which the first kind of impression has been repeatedly associated immediately occurs—this is the essence of causal inference or belief, because a belief is nothing but an idea that is almost as vivid and forceful as the impression of which it was once a copy (I.III.7–8)—and further, there is an actual feeling of the mind (as we would ordinarily say) being tugged from the one impression to the other idea—this is the basis of the idea of necessary connection, a connection which the mind then “spreads” upon its objects to form the idea of a necessary connection among them or their states (I.III.14).

Hume’s theory is a form of epistemological idealism in that it relocates the relation of causation from the external objects where we would ordinarily suppose it to obtain to the mind, which we would ordinarily suppose knows but does not constitute the relation known. In Hume’s words, “Tho the several resembling instances, which give rise to the idea of power, have no influence on each other, and can never produce any new quality in the object , which can be a model of that idea [of power or causation], yet the observation of this resemblance produces a new impression in the mind , which is its real model….Necessity, then, is the effect of this observation, and is nothing but an internal impression of the mind, or a determination to carry our thoughts from one object to another” (I.III.14, para. 20). Several things may be noted about this theory. For one, if it had been Hume’s intent to raise a general skepticism about causation, based on the famous worry about induction that he himself raises, especially in the subsequent Enquiry , namely that an assertion of causality claims that future impressions will occur in the same patterns as past ones but there is no basis “in reason” for assuming that the future will resemble the past, then the relocation of causation from the domain of objects to the domain of the mind should make no difference, because we have no more reason to believe that the mind will behave the same way in the future as it has in the past than we do to believe that about anything else. So we must either believe that Hume is very confused, not realizing that his skepticism about induction as applied to external objects must undermine our confidence in his application of induction to the mind itself, or else that he is very arch, and that he means us to do his skeptical work for him by carrying over skepticism about induction to the case of the mind itself, or else that he is not really worrying about issues of justification and thus of the threat of skepticism at all, but just means to be giving a plausible description of the only possible basis for causal inference, namely the mind’s experience of itself. The last possibility may well seem to be the most plausible, leading to the “naturalist” reading of Hume promoted by Norman Kemp Smith and Barry Stroud rather than the “skeptical” reading of Hume accepted by his contemporaries such as James Beattie and defended recently by Robert Fogelin.

There is a further issue with Hume’s treatment of causation that is largely suppressed in the Enquiry but that was evident in the Treatise , namely, that although, as we saw in the last passage quoted, Hume sometimes presents his epistemological idealism about causation by describing necessary connection as being displaced from the object to the mind, on his own strict interpretation of empiricism there is a problem in positing the existence of either objects or minds distinct from perceptions. This is what pushes Hume towards his own form of ontological idealism. That is, although we naturally speak of perceptions as being of objects and in or by the mind, on the view that all knowledge is founded on perception and that in perception we are immediately acquainted with nothing but perceptions, it becomes problematic how we could have knowledge either of the mind itself or of any object of perceptions distinct from those perceptions. Hume puts the former point succinctly by arguing that we have no perception of the self distinct from our perception of its perceptual states: “For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself , I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I can never catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the perception” ( Treatise I.IV.6.3). He then argues that in fact the self is “nothing but a bundle of different perceptions, which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement” (I.IV.6.4), and that the idea of a continuous self is but a fiction or illusion created by relations of resemblance and continuity among perceptions in the bundle, just as both the idea of and belief in causal connection were created by repetition of pairs of impressions. Without saying that the objects of perception are also nothing but bundles of related perceptions, Hume presents a similar account of how the idea of objects distinct from our perceptions of them is generated by our impression of continuity among perceptions: although only philosophers reflect on this, in fact we know that perceptions are fleeting and transitory; we mistake continuity among them for enduring identity; and we then invent something other than perceptions, something not fleeting and transitory, to which to ascribe that enduring identity ( Treatise, I.IV.2). In neither case, however, do we actually have a clear idea of any object or substance distinct from our perceptions: we do not have such an idea of external objects or their substance, but neither do we have a clear idea of the mind or its substance. The only ideas we have are copies of our impressions, or perceptions.

Hume’s attack on the supposition that we have an idea of the mind as distinct from its impressions thus constitutes a rejection of Berkeley’s commitment to the existence of mental substances, but not of ontological idealism altogether. On Hume’s account, we are not entitled to assert the existence of both ideas and the minds, human or divine, that have them, but only the former. At the same time, he does not seem to think that we are forced into skepticism about either minds or external objects by his approach, that is, into a position that there may really be minds and external objects but we cannot know that fact or their real qualities; yet he still has a lingering worry that although there are psychological mechanisms leading us to form the fictions of minds and bodies beyond perceptions, we do not really know what we are talking about when we talk about such things, and thus cannot even coherently doubt whether we have knowledge of them—our talk about them is explicable but meaningless. Hume thus seems to end up with an uneasy compromise between epistemological idealism and ontological agnosticism, on the one hand, and his own form of ontological idealism on the other.

The first major philosophy actually to call himself an idealist was Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), although as soon as he did so he labored to distinguish his position from Berkeley’s, not using these terms but essentially identifying himself as an epistemological but not ontological idealist. The sources as well as the form of Kant’s idealism are complex. Kant was deeply impressed by what he knew of Leibniz (many of the texts that are crucial to later understandings of Leibniz, such as “Primary Truths”, having been unknown in Kant’s times, or others, such as the New Essays on Human Understanding , having been published only when he was well into his career) and the view that space and time are phaenomena bene fundata and by what he knew of Hume and the view that causation is a form of thinking that we impose upon our experience rather than something we directly experience it. He was more generally impressed by the empiricist argument that our knowledge of objects depends upon experience of them. However, he thought that both the Leibnizian and the Humean approaches failed to account for the possibility of synthetic a priori knowledge, that is, knowledge that goes beyond the mere analysis of concepts, thus does more than merely unpack explicit or tacit definitions, but yet legitimately claims universal and necessary validity. But, unlike Plato, the original apriorist avant la letter , he does not see synthetic a priori knowledge as leading to realism about objects having the features that we know a priori , nor, like Malebranche, the theological Platonist, does he see such knowledge as knowledge of the mind of God; rather, he sees it as providing the conclusive argument for epistemological idealism through the premise that we can only know to be necessary and therefore universally valid the forms that we ourselves impose upon our experience. At the same time, even though when he wrote his main works he was not well-informed on the aporia about subjects and objects about which Hume had ultimately thrown up his arms in the Treatise , which has here been characterized as the tension in Hume between agnosticism and ontological idealism, Kant recognized that we cannot talk about what he called appearances without conceding the real existence of subjects to which objects appear as well as the objects that appear to such subjects. Kant was thus led to what he called “transcendental idealism,” a position that combines epistemological idealism about the main structures of objects, that is, the view that we ourselves impose spatiality, temporality, substantiality, causality, and other forms upon our experience and precisely because we know these forms a priori cannot regard them as also the real forms of objects independent of ourselves, with a kind of ontological realism, the view that in some sense our selves and our objects really do exist independently of our representations of them. Though he identifies his own “transcendental idealism” with “empirical realism” he does not want to call his own position “transcendental realism,” because for him that would be the view that objects independent of our representations do exist with the forms that we represent them as having, thus a form of epistemological realism rather than idealism. Neither would he even be happy to call that part of his position ontological idealism in the sense in which we have been using that terminology here, because it is part of his position that, at least from a theoretical point of view, we cannot suppose that even our own minds are really as they appear to us, nor can we assert that the reality that ultimately underlies the appearance of minds is essentially different from the reality that ultimately underlies the appearance of bodies. But he is confident that we are entitled to assert the existence of some sort of reality underlying the appearance of both minds and bodies, so that epistemological idealism must be accompanied by some sort of ontology, even if only an indeterminate one.

Kant had already published a number of substantial scientific as well as philosophical works before the “great light” of transcendental idealism came to him in 1769, leading to his first statement of it the following year in his inaugural dissertation, On the Forms and Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible Worlds (1770). But it would then take him another decade, the so-called “silent decade”, to publish his full argument for transcendental idealism in the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason , which appeared in 1781, and even then the relation between the epistemological idealism that he developed in that work and ontology continued to vex him: the first substantial review of the book in 1782 charged him with Berkeleianism, in other words, with the addition of ontological idealism to epistemological idealism, and Kant then tried to rebut that accusation in his attempted popularization of the Critique , the Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics of 1783, and to further defend that rebuttal of ontological idealism in the “Refutation of Idealism” that he added to the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787. Even then he was not done with the subject, as we know from a dozen further drafts of the “Refutation” that he composed after that second edition of the Critique . Indeed, Kant continued to struggle with the clarification of his own position to the end of his life, attempting a restatement of transcendental idealism in the uncompleted material for a final book that has come down to us under the name of the Opus postumum . But since it was Kant’s presentations of his position in the two editions of the Critique and the Prolegomena that were most influential in his own time and have been since, we shall concentrate on those texts here.

Kant’s arguments for his transcendental idealism are distributed across all parts of his Critique of Pure Reason . He gives a direct argument for it in the Transcendental Aesthetic, supplemented by the Transcendental Analytic, and he gives an indirect argument for it in the Transcendental Dialectic by arguing that only his transcendental idealism can allow us to avoid the paradoxes or confusions of traditional metaphysics. We will comment first on Kant’s direct argument for transcendental idealism and then on his indirect argument for it through the critique of traditional metaphysics.

The direct argument is based on Kant’s claim, substantiated in the Transcendental Aesthetic, that we necessarily represent space and time and objects in them by means of our a priori representations of space and time, which are thus pure forms for the intuition of particular objects, and we can construct proofs of theorems about space and time by appeal to our a priori representations or in “pure intuition”. But how does this lead to idealism? Kant’s chief argument is that space and time can represent “no property at all of any things in themselves nor any relations of them to each other, i.e., no determination of them that attaches to objects themselves and that would remain even if one were to abstract from all subjective conditions of intuition”, and that space and time themselves can instead be only our a priori representations of them and the spatial and temporal features of objects in space and time only features of our representations of them or of the “appearances” of objects, because “neither absolute nor relative determinations can be intuited prior to the existence of the things to which they pertain, thus be intuited a priori ” (A 26/B 42). The decisive point of this argument is the following: although because of our forms of intuition our particular representations necessarily have spatio-temporal structure, any objects that had that structure independently of our so representing them would at best have such structure contingently , and thus the supposedly synthetic a priori propositions about space, time, and their mathematics would not be necessarily true throughout their domain. Kant makes this key point several times. In the Critique , he poses the rhetorical question, “If there did not lie in you a faculty for intuiting a priori ; if this subjective condition were not at the same time the universal a priori condition under which alone the object of…intuition is possible; if the object ([e.g.,] the triangle) were something in itself without relation to your subject: then how could you say that what necessarily lies in your subjective conditions for constructing a triangle must also necessarily pertain to the triangle in itself” (A 48/B 65). Similarly, in the Prolegomena he writes that “Pure mathematics, and especially pure geometry, can have objective reality only under the single condition that it refers merely to objects of the senses, with regard to which objects, however, the principle remains fixed, that our sensory representation is by no means a representation of things in themselves, but only of the way in which they appear to us”, for on the contrary supposition “it absolutely would not follow from the representation of [e.g.] space, a representation that serves a priori , with all the various properties of space, as foundation for the geometer, that all of this, together with what is deduced from it, must be exactly so in nature. The space of the geometer would [or could] be taken for mere fabrication and credited with no objective validity, because it is simply not to be seen how things would have to agree necessarily with the image that we form of them by ourselves and in advance” (§13, Note I, 4:287). So, Kant concludes, in order to be necessarily true throughout their domain, the synthetic a priori propositions about space and time—and this includes not just the specific propositions of geometry or mathematics more generally but also the general propositions derived in the metaphysical expositions, such as that space and time are infinite singular wholes with parts rather than instances—must be true only of the representations on which we impose our own forms of intuition, and cannot be true of things as they are in themselves. This is Kant’s chief argument for epistemological idealism, the view that the way things appear to us essentially reflects our cognitive capacities rather anything intrinsic to them, combined with indeterminate ontological realism, the view that there are things independent of our representations of them but because our most fundamental ways of representing things cannot be true of them we cannot know anything about them other than this fact itself.

In a passage added to the second edition of the Critique, Kant also points out that by arguing for the “transcendental ideality” of spatio-temporality—that it is a necessary feature of our representations of things but not a feature of things as they are in themselves at all—he does not mean to degrade space to a “mere illusion”, as did “the good Berkeley” (B 71): his position is that it is a subjective but necessary feature of our way of representing things, similar to secondary qualities such as color or fragrance (B 70n) in being subjective but unlike them in being necessary (see also A 29/B 45), and he thinks that by failing to see that the spatiality (in particular) of our representations is necessary, Berkeley has unnecessarily “demoted” it to a mere illusion. Kant’s larger objection to the charge that his position is not different from Berkeley’s is, however, that while denying the spatiality and temporality of things as they are in themselves, he has provided no reason to deny that there are things distinct from our representations of them and our own minds as representing them. But since this larger objection is most clearly expounded and defended in the Prolegomena and the “Refutation of Idealism” added to the second edition of the Critique , which is inserted into the Transcendental Analytic, discussion of it can be deferred for now.

Kant does not need to mount a separate argument for transcendental idealism in the Transcendental Analytic, because while that is aimed at showing that the use of certain concepts (the categories of pure understanding) and principles (the principles of pure understanding) are necessary conditions of any cognition of objects at all, indeed of self-consciousness (apperception) itself, but also yield knowledge only when applied to intuitions, pure intuitions in the case of pure mathematical cognition and empirical intuitions in the case of everything else (thus Kant’s famous statement “Without sensibility no object would be given to us, and without understanding none would be thought. Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind”; A 51/B 75), since empirical intuitions have already been shown to yield appearances rather than things in themselves, it automatically follows that the categories and principles of pure understanding will also yield cognition only of appearances. Nevertheless, Kant reaffirms transcendental idealism during the course of the Transcendental Analytic.

The Transcendental Dialectic, the second half of the Critique of Pure Reason in which Kant provides the critique of traditional metaphysics is explicitly intended to give an indirect proof of transcendental idealism (B xx). Specifically, the middle section of the Dialectic, entitled “The Antinomy of Pure Reason”, is supposed to provide this indirect proof. All three sections of the Dialectic, thus the preceding “Paralogisms of Pure Reason” and the following “Ideal of Pure Reason”, are supposed to show that the faculty of reason’s inevitable conception of the “unconditioned”, that which is a condition for everything else but itself has no condition, can never provide knowledge of any object because knowledge requires intuition as well as concept, and intuition is always conditioned—the representation of any region of space is conditioned by more surrounding it, and that of any region of time is likewise conditioned by the representation of more time before and after it. Reason can form “transcendental ideas”, more properly, “transcendent concepts” (A 327/B 384), that is, the ideas of an unconditioned subject (the self as substance), an unconditioned whole of all things and events (a completed world-whole), and an unconditioned ground of all possibility (God) (A 334/B 393). These ideas, according to Kant, may be useful as guidelines for scientific research and even necessary for the purposes of practical reason, but they outrun the limits of intuition and therefore theoretical cognition. This general claim itself does not entail transcendental idealism, that is, it does not identify space and time with our own forms of intuition. However, Kant’s claim is that the paradoxes diagnosed in the “Antinomy of Pure Reason” can only be resolved on the basis of transcendental idealism. In the case of the first two antinomies he argues that both sides essentially concern space and time or the things in them, and that since space and time as forms of intuition are indefinitely extendable and divisible, both sides of the debates, the theses and the antitheses, are false: space and time and thus the totality of things and events in them (the world) are neither bounded and finite or unbounded and infinite but indefinite (even though particular things within space or periods within time may have determinate boundaries). In the case of the third and fourth antinomies, however, Kant argues that the distinction between appearances and things in themselves that is at the heart of transcendental idealism makes it possible for both sides to be considered true, since they concern different objects: in the empirical world of experience, there are only ever indefinitely extending chains of causes and effects, each moment of which is necessary relative to its causal laws (the third antithesis) but contingent because no antecedent cause is absolutely necessary or necessary considered in itself, but outside of the empirical world there is nothing to prevent there being an absolutely necessary thing in itself (God) nor acts of absolute spontaneity on the part of that absolutely necessary being or even lesser beings, such as finite agents. Again, Kant’s claim will ultimately be that we have necessary and sufficient practical grounds for affirming both our own freedom and the existence of God, but these do not yield theoretical cognition (B xxx).

Kant’s antinomies led to the dialectical methods of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, and were thus to prove immensely influential. But it was clearly controversial whether the antinomies in fact required the distinction between appearances and things in themselves; Hegel, for example, surely thought not. For the argument that only transcendental idealism can resolve the antinomies seems to be circular: unless one assumes that our representations of space and time give us not only reliable but also complete information about the nature of space and time and all things in them, there is no reason to assume that the limits of our representations of space and time—their indefiniteness and the contingency of any starting- or stopping-point in them—are also in fact true of space and time and everything in them in themselves. Kant’s indirect proof for transcendental idealism therefore is not conclusive.

Kant himself did not think so, of course. He was utterly committed to transcendental idealism. When confronted with the challenge that transcendental idealism was nothing but Berkeleianism, however, that is, the reduction of all reality to ideas and the minds that have them, he recoiled. This objection was made in the first substantial review of the first edition of the Critique , written from an empiricist point of view by Christian Garve and then redacted by J.H. Feder in 1782 (in Sassen 2000). Kant defended himself by a more precise formulation of his doctrine in the Prolegomena (1783) and further by the insertion of a “Refutation of Idealism”, specifically “material idealism”, into the Transcendental Analytic in the second edition of the Critique (1787). Kant’s claim in the Prolegomena is that his position should be called “formal” or “critical” idealism rather than “material” idealism because it merely identifies space and time with our forms of intuition but does not otherwise deny the reality of the objects in space and time. As he puts it: “There are things given to us as objects of our senses existing outside us, yet we know nothing of them as they may be in themselves, but are acquainted only with their appearances, i.e., with the representations that they produce in us because they affect our senses. Accordingly, I by all means avow that there are bodies outside us, i.e., things which, though completely unknown to us as to what they may be in themselves, we know through the representations which their influence on our sensibility provides for us, and to which we give the name of a body—which word therefore merely signifies the appearance of this object that is unknown to us but is nonetheless real. Can this be called idealism? It is the very opposite of it” (4:288–9). At this stage, Kant’s response to the identification of his position with traditional ontological idealism is basically incredulity: he cannot understand it because in his view he has only given reasons for removing space and time from things to our representations of them, just as earlier philosophers had given (different) reasons for relocating properties like color from object to subject, but has provided no arguments against the existence of those things themselves, which he, like any other sane person, takes for granted.

By the time of the second edition of the Critique , however, Kant must have come to see the need for a positive defense of the assumption of the existence of things in themselves that ground our spatio-temporal representations of body (although, since those things in themselves are not supposed to be spatio-temporal and causality is supposed to be a spatio-temporal relation, they cannot precisely be said to cause our spatio-temporal representations). Kant’s argument—which in the following years Kant would attempt to improve a dozen times (see Guyer 1983 and Kant 2005)—is that we can only achieve “empirically determined consciousness” of our own existence, or a determinate temporal ordering of our own representations, by correlating them with something enduring outside of and distinct from them: “The perception of this persistent thing is possible only through a thing outside me and not through the mere representation of a thing outside me” (B 275). Spatiality may be acknowledged to be only my way of representing things outside me, but insofar as anything in space is used to determine the order of my own representations it must be regarded as being ontologically distinct from my representations of it even if its phenomenology is subjective, that is, even if spatiality is only our way of representing ontological independence (see A 22/B 37). In this way he proves, contra Berkeley who denies it and Descartes who doubts it, that our phenomenologically spatial representations are “grounded” in something ontologically distinct from those representations. Kant’s “Refutation” was intended precisely to demonstrate that epistemological idealism, the argument that our most basic forms of knowledge in fact reflect only our own forms of intuition and conceptualization, could and must be combined with indeterminate ontological realism.

It may well be asked of Kant’s “Refutation of Idealism”, as it had already been asked of his yet-to-be-named transcendental idealism in 1770 by such distinguished contemporaries as Johann Heinrich Lambert, Johann Georg Sulzer, and Moses Mendelssohn, whether it is really compatible with the transcendental ideality of time , that is, whether it does not presuppose the reality of the temporality of the enduring object it proposes by means of which to determine the sequence of our own representations as well as of the self that has that sequence of representations (isn’t the sequence of representations, they essentially asked, really a sequence?). But we will not further pursue that question here, because all of Kant’s successors were more concerned with the viability of Kant’s general distinction between appearances and things in themselves rather than with the specifics of Kant’s argument for transcendental idealism from a priori knowledge or of Kant’s proof that we can assert the existence of things in themselves in spite of that distinction. This concern began with the famous objection of F.H. Jacobi, made in the appendix to his 1787 book on David Hume, that without the assumption of things in themselves he could not enter into the critical system, but that with it he could not remain within the system; that is, he felt that once the distinction between appearances and things in themselves was made all ground for the assumption of the existence of things other than our own representations was removed even if Kant had made no explicit argument against that existence. So let us now turn to Kant’s successors to see how they tried to save Kant’s insight into the idea that the most fundamental forms of knowledge ultimately depend on fundamental operations of self-consciousness—the basic insight of epistemological idealism—without ending up with Kant’s combination of that with indeterminate ontological realism.

Kant can thus be seen to have made two major points concerning epistemological and ontological idealism, although again these are not his terms. (1) As far as ontological idealism is concerned, although he never questions the existence of something independent of our representations of it, he can claim to have shown that when it comes to the ultimate constitution of this reality as it may be considered independently of the way it appears to beings endowed with reason and (human) sensibility we can know nothing (on theoretical grounds; on practical grounds, he insisted, we can infer, for example, that we really are free). We neither can know whether—to use a Hobbesian expression again—“ without us” or—to use Kant’s own term “ in itself ”—there are material objects around that consist of substances and their attributes standing in spatio-temporal or other (e.g. causal) relations to each other and constituting a law-governed whole called nature. Nor can we know whether whatever we experience as an object is in the end some mental product of a divine mind having creative powers totally different from those we can make sense of. Thus we are bound to be agnostic with regard to any metaphysical theoretical claims as to the real constitution of the world, and this implies that there is no way to convince us of either ontological idealism or determinate ontological realism. (2) However, following Kant, things are different in the case of epistemological idealism. Whenever we talk about objects of cognition, i.e., of objects that are addressed by us in terms of concepts and judgments, we have to accept them as being conceptual constructions based on our subjective forms of intuitions and on very specific conceptual rules for bringing together or unifying data: an object of cognition is that “in whose concept a manifold of what is given through sensibility is united” ( Critique of Pure Reason , B 137). This means, according to Kant, that idealism in epistemology is inescapable, because the assumption of the conceptual constitution of objects of cognition is unavoidable.

Kant’s Solomonic verdict was not much appreciated by the main representatives of post-Kantian German idealism. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, as already mentioned, immediately criticized Kant’s allowance of things in themselves of unknown determinations, and replaced it with a straightforward fideism about external existence (which he alleged to find in Hume’s rejection of the psychological possibility of skepticism). However, the general tendency of the idealists, beginning with Johann Gottlieb Fichte, was to overcome the distinction between ontological and epistemological idealism and to show that there is no real opposition between what is traditionally taken to be a subject-independent world that is present to us in the mode of ‘givenness’ and ‘being’ and a world that is conceived of as subject-dependent in that it is formed by conceptual tools or other ‘thought-ingredients’ stemming from some subjective activity or other. This led to a new conception of idealism whose distinguishing character consists in the endorsement of the claim of the “inseparability of being and thinking”. This conception was realized by introducing entirely new ways of thinking about what ultimately constitutes reality based on a dynamic conception of self-consciousness that the German idealists took to be at the heart of Kant’s theory of the transcendental unity of apperception (and arrived at by Kant out of epistemological , not: ontological, considerations!). According to this conception, reality has to be conceived as a result of an activity paradigmatically manifested in the unique manner in which consciousness of oneself arises. In order to find out the true nature of reality one has to gain insight into the operations of this activity.

This approach to answering fundamental metaphysical questions by casting into doubt the traditional distinction between ontology and epistemology not only leads to a different conception of what idealism is all about. Above all, it means that one has to sketch out the difference between idealism and whatever is taken to be its opposite (realism, naturalism, materialism, sensualism etc.) not in terms of different kinds of “stuff” either material or mental; dynamic elements like activities and forces must be the primary constituents of reality rather than more substantial items like material objects and (spiritual) persons. Idealism understood in this fashion becomes the name of a “metaphysical” (in a non-traditional sense) world-view that is opposed to what especially Fichte and Schelling liked to call “dogmatism” and is rooted in assumptions about dynamic processes that are operative in the course of self- and object-constitution. There is thus a fundamental difference between the idealism of German idealism and the immaterialism of Berkeley: where Berkeley’s idealism focused on ideas as the “stuff” of existence and assumed minds, whether human or divine, as their repository, the German idealists focused on the mind as active and largely tried to suppress the traditional ontology of substances and their accidents within which Berkeley still worked, which Hume questioned but for which he supplied no alternative, and which Kant again defended by conceiving of substance and accident as relational categories.

Although the overcoming of the distinction between ontological and epistemological idealism by means of relying on self-relating activities might be seen as a common goal of all the major German idealistic thinkers, they pursued this project in very different directions. The first post-Kantian philosopher who embarked explicitly on the project to elaborate a dynamic idealistic conception of reality built on a specific conception of self-consciousness was Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814) while he was a professor at the university of Saxe-Weimar in Jena from 1794 to 1799. In his Doctrine of Science (1794/95) and in the First and Second Introduction into the Doctrine of Science (1797) he famously set out to demonstrate that the primordial act of self-positing lies at the basis of all reality. His starting point is an epistemological question: how does it come that we cannot help but experience objective reality the way we do, i.e. in terms of spatio-temporal objects standing in determinate relations? Where do these representations of objects, of relations and especially the belief that they exist come from? In order to answer these questions we must, according to Fichte, accept three fundamental principles ( Grundsätze ) without which we could not even make sense of the idea that there is something real at all. The first states that self-consciousness or the I is a spontaneous (unconditioned) act that in taking place creates or posits the I as having existence or being ( ein Akt, der im Vollzug sein eigenes Sein schafft ). The I understood as this self-positing act that gives rise to its own being and reality Fichte characterizes as “deed-act” ( Tathandlung ), and it is through this deed-act that what we take to be real or having being comes to the fore. The second principle postulates a necessary act of counter-positing ( Entgegensetzen ) to the self-positing activity of the I resulting in what Fichte calls a Non-I. This principle is meant to establish the possibility of the reality of “otherness,” of something which is not the I. The third principle shows how to mediate between the self-positing and the counter-positing acts of the I by reciprocal limitation, thereby introducing a subject-object opposition within the I. On the basis of these three principles and by reflecting on the purported interplay between self-positing and counter-positing in a highly original way, Fichte arrives at a portrait of reality in which all “ordinary” objects, like walls, trees and people, and their “normal” interactions and dependencies, like causal, spatio-temporal, and physical force relations, find a place. This portrait is claimed to be idealistic because it is the outcome of an insight into the dynamics of these fundamental and opposed positing acts and because in the end these activities, according to Fichte, are, metaphysically speaking, all there is: “for the philosopher there is acting, and nothing but acting; because, as a philosopher, he thinks idealistically” ( Second Introduction , section 7; Werke I, 498). Idealism thus starts to become what could be called from a traditional point of view a “hybrid” position that intimately connects epistemological and ontological elements in that it “explains … the determinations of consciousness”. i.e., our common sense conception of reality, “out of the acting of the intellect [ Intelligenz ]” without thinking of the intellect as some sort of existing subject: “For idealism the intellect is an acting and absolutely nothing else; one should not even call it something active because by this expression one points to something substantial which is the subject of this activity” ( First Introduction , section 7, Werke I, 440). A consequence that Fichte explicitly draws from this understanding of idealism is that one can no longer think of realism as a position that is opposed to idealism. Rather “realism, … i.e., the assumption that objects totally independently of us exist outside of us, is contained in idealism itself and becomes explained and deduced in it” ( Second Introduction , footnote at end of section 1, Werke I, 455). Because in Fichte’s metaphysical world everything is based on the I as a pure activity, it is not that surprising that his idealism very often was called “subjective idealism”, even though he would resist any identification with Berkeley’s substance-accident form of immaterialism. He avoids that conception by introducing what could be called an ontology of pure action.

Fichte’s dynamic conception of idealism was adopted almost immediately by Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775–1854), who in the first period of his philosophical career became next to Fichte the most outspoken defender of this hybrid variety of idealism. In doing so he transformed Fichte’s I-centered approach to reality into an idealistic version of a monistic ontology. In this he was followed by Hegel. Whereas Fichte had mainly struggled to find an adequate expression for his activity-based conception of a self-positing I and had referred to anything outside the I only as the non-I posited by the I itself, in his early writings on the philosophy of nature Schelling tries to supplement Fichte’s approach by giving a much fuller account of nature, understood as everything that appears to be independent of us, in terms of the I-constituting activities. Because of Schelling’s elevation of nature to a central topic in his presentation of an idealistic worldview his position became characterized, although somewhat misleadingly, as “objective idealism”. On his account, we have to think of reality as an original unity ( ursprüngliche Einheit ) or a primordial totality ( uranfängliche Ganzheit ) of opposites that is internally differentiated such that every particular item within reality can be seen as a partial, incomplete, or one-sided expression, manifestation, or interpretation of the most basic dynamic opposition characteristic of the whole of reality. This view of reality, which in early Schelling is quite explicitly linked to Spinoza’s one-substance ontology, obviously does not lead directly to any idealism whatsoever: one could just as well give it a naturalistic reading. In order to connect a monistic ontology to idealism, one has to somehow identify the activities at work in the constitution of the world-whole with mental or spiritual elements that are supposed to give conceptual structure to reality. This can be and was done by Schelling at different stages of his philosophical career in different ways. In the first edition of his Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature ( Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Natur ) (1797), he set out to prove idealism by trying to show that “the system of Nature is at the same time the system of our mind” ( IP 30, SW 1, 134). This claim is not meant to state a reciprocal relation of dependence between nature and mind and their characteristic features, i.e., according to Schelling, matter and concept, thereby presupposing that nature and mind, matter and concept nevertheless have some reality independently of each other. He rather wants us to think of nature and mind, matter and concept as being identical in the sense of being the same: the one is the other and vice versa. The reason why we as finite minds have to differentiate between them at all lies in a double perspective which is forced on us by our natural predisposition to distinguish the “outside us” from the “in us” (cf. IP 39; SW 1, 138) when looking at reality—thus Schelling sees dualism as a psychological tendency but not a philosophical option. If this disposition and its conditions were understood in the right way, we would comprehend that, as he famously writes, “Nature should be made Mind visible, Mind the invisible Nature” ( IP 42; SW 1, 151) thereby making room for an idealistic conception of reality as World-Soul ( World-Soul is also the title of a 1798 publication by Schelling).

As a systematic counterpart to the construction of the phenomena of nature out of different dynamic factors (forces, activities), in 1800 Schelling presented his System of Transcendental Idealism . Here he set out to demonstrate the development of mental phenomena out of these factors which he here calls the unconscious and the conscious activity starting with sensation ( Empfindung ) and intuition ( Anschauung ) until he arrives via acts of willing at the aesthetic activity manifested in works of art. He thinks of these transcendental idealistic demonstrations as a necessary complement to his philosophy of nature (cf. SW III, 331 f.) and describes their mutual relation thus: “As the philosophy of nature brings idealism forth out of realism, in that it spiritualizes the laws of nature into laws of intelligence, or adds the formal to the material, so does transcendental philosophy bring realism out of idealism, by materializing the laws of intelligence into laws of nature , or adds the material to the form“ ( SW III, 352). On this conception both together, philosophy of nature and transcendental idealism, exhaust the entire scope of philosophy, which reveals itself in the end to be nothing but a “progressive history of self-consciousness” ( fortgehende Geschichte des Selbstbewusstseins ) ( SW III 331).

This early approach to establishing an idealistic monism and thereby vindicating a Fichte-inspired dynamic version of ontological idealism was in turn given up by Schelling a couple of years later in the second edition of the Ideas and criticized by him as providing a basis only for what he now calls “relative idealism” ( IP 52; SW 1, 163). It is replaced by what he now names “absolute idealism” ( IP 50; SW 1, 162). Both his criticism of his earlier World-Soul conception and his endorsement of absolute idealism are at least to a certain degree due to Hegel’s discussion of Schelling’s philosophy in his Difference between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy (1801). Schelling’s new conception, which underlies what came to be known as his “System of Identity” ( Identitätssystem ), takes reality to be a dynamic whole which he describes as the “undivorced” ( ungeschieden ) or undifferentiated unity of the absolute-ideal or subjectivity and the absolute-real or objectivity in an “eternal act of cognition” ( IP 47; SW 1, 157). This eternal act is all there is, it is “the absolute”. It is disclosed in two fundamentally different forms, one of which is characterized by the prevalence of subjectivity whereas in the other form objectivity prevails. These two forms give rise to the distinction between an “ideal world” and “Nature” ( IP 49; SW 1, 161). However, according to Schelling these forms have to be distinguished from the “eternal cognitive act” or the absolute from which the ideal world and Nature originate. This act is pure activity of knowing that creates its objects in the very act of cognition by giving them a form. Because reality is conceived thus as a dynamic self-organizing cognitive process that lies at the basis of even the most fundamental opposition between subject and object, Schelling thinks of his ontological monism as a version of idealism. He writes: “If we therefore define philosophy as a whole according to that wherein it surveys and presents everything, namely the absolute act of cognition, of which even Nature is again only one side, the Idea of all ideas, then it is Idealism. Idealism is and remains, therefore, the whole of philosophy, and only under itself does the latter again comprehend idealism and realism, save that the first absolute Idealism is not to be confused with this other, which is of a merely relative kind” ( IP 50; SW 1, 162). In the end, then, after 1800 Schelling (arguably as well as Fichte in his post-Jena period) seems pushed toward a “non-dogmatic” idealism that combines ontological as well as epistemological idealism within a monistic framework.

Although Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) too embraces a dynamical conception of reality in the spirit of Fichte and Schelling, he deviates from both of them by not relying on mental activities of some subject or other or on some primordial subjectless cognitive act as the most basic features of reality. Given his deep distrust of irreconcilable dichotomies, of anything unmediated and one-sided, one cannot expect Hegel to be an advocate of an idea of idealism that is conceived of in terms of an alternative to or an opposition against realism or materialism or whatever else. He thus shares with Fichte and Schelling the hostility against any attempts to privilege idealism over and against realism (or something else) or the other way round, but avoids the suspicion of a reversion to ontological idealism in a monistic guise better than either of his predecessors. In the case of Hegel, this hostility towards privileging ontological idealism shows especially well in his criticism of reductive programs as well as of “bifurcating” ( entzweiend ) or separating positions in metaphysics and epistemology. A reductive program according to which either everything physical/material is reducible to something mental and thus confirms idealism or everything mental can be reduced to something physical/material and thus gives rise to realism or materialism is in his eyes “ridiculous” (cf. GW 6, 290 ff). A bifurcating or separating position results from a project that is based on the claim that one has to distinguish between a world “for us” and a world “in itself”, where the former is a subject-dependent and in this sense idealistic world while the latter is the “real” world although it is essentially totally inaccessible by any subjective cognitive means. It is because of its one-sidedness and its putting “the real” outside of our grasp that such a “subjective” idealism is for Hegel unacceptable (see his criticism of Kant in Faith and Knowledge , GW 4, 325 ff.). His objections to and his contempt for both idealism and realism in their mutually exclusive forms are well documented in almost all of his writings throughout his philosophical career.

Thus, when Hegel in the second edition of his Science of Logic (1831) nevertheless claims that in the end “[e]very philosophy is essentially idealism or at least has it as its principle” ( GW 21, 142), he must mean by idealism something other than ontological idealism and certainly something other than Kant’s indeterminate ontological realism. Rather, he must mean by idealism a philosophical outlook that is immune against the charge of grounding a philosophical system in a conception of reality that is committed to the acceptance of any irreconcilable oppositions. Now, for Hegel the most fundamental opposition both from a systematic and a historical perspective is the opposition between thinking and being. Looked at from a systematic perspective, this opposition is fundamental because of its apparent unavoidability, already at a descriptive level, when it comes to an assessment of the ultimate characteristics of reality: after all, we want to be able to hold fast to the distinction between what is only (in) our (subjective) thought and what is (objectively) the case. Considered from a historical point of view it shows that—at least within the tradition of occidental philosophy—the opposition between thinking and being lies at the bottom of the most influential attempts (with very few exceptions like Parmenides and possibly Spinoza) to give a philosophical account of the essence of reality and its multifarious ways of appearing to us. The traditional conviction of the fundamental and irreconcilable opposition between thinking and being finds expression in many different ways. These ways include the belief that there is being that is totally independent of or without any relation to thinking, or the conviction that thinking is somehow external to being in that being is just the self-standing provider of material on which a by itself contentless ( inhaltslos ) thinking imposes a certain conceptual form, or the assumption that even if there were no thinking there would be being and vice versa. However, according to Hegel it can be demonstrated that to think of thinking and being as fundamentally opposed in any of these ways leads to inconsistencies resulting in contradictions, antinomies and other bewildering deficiencies. Hence an idealistic philosophical system that is to overcome these deficiencies has to get rid of the underlying fundamental opposition and to show that thinking and being are not opposed but ultimately the same. This claim as to the sameness or the identity of thinking and being is the cornerstone of Hegel’s metaphysical credo and together with some other assumptions leads relatively smoothly to a version of ontological monism as the only convincing shape of an idealistic system. Thus, while accepting monism and rejecting Kantian dualism, Hegel refuses to accept an absolute distinction between mind and non-mind and thus refuses to make his monism mentalistic in the way that he believes both Fichte and Schelling ultimately did, even if their mentalistic conceptions were activity- rather than substance-based.

It is important to notice however, that an ontological monism conceived along these lines is not meant to translate directly into the claim according to which reality because of its opposition-transcending nature is characterized by oneness, individuality or singularity. Rather, Hegel’s ontological monism and thus his idealism is meant to be a claim as to the constitution of what is real in reality, a claim about what constitutes the essence (the “truth”) of real objects. According to him, it makes no sense to divorce thinking from being in our conception of objects because every object is best understood as an original unity of both thought-determinations and specific ways of being. His monism thus is not founded primarily in a conviction as to the ultimate constitution of reality conceived of as an all-encompassing totality or as a quasi-Spinozistic substance (although in the end he will extend his monism to apply even to traditional totalities), but relates first of all to his belief in the ontological inseparability of thinking and being in an individual object. For Hegel to grasp the idea of objects as “thought-things” ( Gedankensachen ) or “thing-thoughts”’ ( Sachgedanken )—he sometimes uses the expression “objective thoughts” (e.g. Encyclopedia , § 24; GW 20, 67)—is a necessary condition for being able to give a systematic account of the constitution and the organization of all the different types of objects together with their relational characteristics both concerning their internal states and their external connections.

In later years, Hegel seems to have been well aware that it might be a bit confusing to call a position which refuses to draw a sharp distinction between thinking and being an idealistic position. After all, the connotations of the term “idealism” in the era of Kant and the earlier post-Kantians could have led to the expectation that in favoring or in devising an idealistic approach to what objects and reality have to be one has to agree that there is a certain priority to thinking in the constitution of objects and their collective behavior. Thus it is not really surprising that, late in life, Hegel shows some sympathy with calling a position like his own an “Ideal-realism” ( Idealrealismus ), emphasizing thereby the ontological inseparability between thinking and being. This sympathy is documented in one of his last reviews for his Jahrbücher für wissenschaftliche Kritik , i.e. his review of A. L. J. Ohlert: Der Idealrealismus. Erster Theil. Der Idealrealismus als Metaphysik. In die Stelle des Idealismus und Realismus gesetzt ( GW 16, 287 ff.).

Hegel’s basic claim as to the identity of thinking and being in the object might be said to have some initial plausibility if one takes such a claim to be a somewhat metaphorical expression of the view that in our ways of thinking about objects some conceptual elements are invariably involved. Understood along these lines, Hegel’s claim could be considered, as it often is, as nothing but a peculiar version of Kant’s epistemological idealism. Such an interpretation might even be suggested by the impression that Hegel as well as Kant takes thinking to be an activity that is characterized by operating on and with concepts and that what Hegel calls “being” can easily be identified with what within Kant’s epistemological framework is called “reality”, that is, the empirical reality of intuited objects rather than their transcendent grounds. Although this impression is by no means entirely groundless, it is still misleading because it does not do justice to the ontological connotations that Hegel wants to connect with this claim. For Hegel it is indeed essential to convince us that it is a demonstrable fact that objects in the world are realized concepts. Obviously this view as to what objects really are—if it is not meant to be just another variation of either a dogmatic idealist claim in the spirit of Berkeley or a subjective (epistemological) idealism à la Kant—has to use the terms “concept” and “real” in a way that is different from their traditional or normal use in the history of modern philosophy since Descartes. And so it is. For Hegel a concept is not a general representation in the mind of a subject nor is the term “real” meant to be restricted to hinting at the presence of some type of matter either physical or mental. Rather, Hegel thinks of concepts as providing what could be called “structure plans” for objects, and he takes the term “real” to designate the successful realization of a structure plan or a concept; thus Hegel attempts to use these terms in a teleological sense without any mentalistic (i.e. psychological or representationalistic) ontological commitments. Although these somewhat unconventional connotations of Hegel’s concepts of “concept” and ”real” (which have a certain basis in a peculiar German use of these terms) might be confusing, they are—at least in his eyes—by no means without descriptive value. Thus, to use examples that Hegel mentions in the Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit , it makes perfectly good sense to describe a fully grown oak-tree as the realization of what is contained as genetic structure in the acorn out of which the tree has developed or to think of a political state as a realization of what belongs to the concept of a state making the state a realized concept or an “objective thought”. However, although these examples can throw some light on why Hegel might think of his approach as leading to an ideal-realistic conception of reality, the idealistic aspect of his view strictly speaking has to do with his theory as to what these concepts of which every object is a realization are supposed to be. These concepts have to be taken as themselves being determinate manifestations of different determinations of what Hegel calls “the Concept”. Here the Concept is conceived of as providing something like the master plan or the universal structure that governs not only the conceptual structure of individual kinds of objects but the structure of individual objects as well. This universal structure comes about by means of a process of conceptual self-determination that results in a complete exposition of the conceptual elements contained in the Concept. This process of self-determination is understood by Hegel as the way in which the Concept realizes itself. After all, the Concept, being a thought-object or an object-thought itself, must also have reality or being and thus has to realize itself.

Although Hegel definitely wants to overcome what he takes to be shortcomings both of Kant’s philosophy and of the positions of his post-Kantian contemporaries Fichte and Schelling, at the same time he does not want to give up on the post-Kantian project of transforming Kant’s subjective epistemological idealism into a robust new idealism based on dynamic principles of world-constitution. He differs from Fichte and Schelling in that he does not ground these principles either in some activity of a subject (Fichte) or in a cognitively inaccessible primordial unity (Schelling) but in the idea of a thoroughly conceptual organization of reality giving rise to what he calls in the introduction to the second edition of the Science of Logic an “intellectual view of the universe” ( Intellektualansicht des Universums ) ( GW 21, 34). In this way, Hegel does try to reconcile the need for conceptual elements constitutive of traditional epistemological idealism with (most of) the categorical commitments characteristic of traditional ontological idealism yet in a way that no longer requires the opposition between epistemology and ontology.

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) heaped a great deal of invective on Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. And indeed, nothing could be further from Hegel’s version of absolute idealism than Schopenhauer’s theory on which behind the realm of appearances constructed in accordance with our own conceptions of space, time, and causality—his form of epistemological idealism—there is a unitary reality that is utterly irrational or at least arational—his form of ontological realism. Schopenhauer puts forward his theory in his main work The World as Will and Representation , first published in December, 1818 (with an 1819 date on its title page), and then in a much-expanded second edition in 1844 and yet another expanded edition in 1857. This book had been preceded by a doctoral dissertation On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason (1813), which Schopenhauer subsequently regarded as the introduction to his magnum opus. The earlier work includes Schopenhauer’s main modifications to the structure of Kant’s epistemology, while the later work accepts Kant’s idealist interpretation of this epistemology (Book I) and then replaces Kant’s version of the doctrine of things in themselves with Schopenhauer’s own version of the unitary non-rational will underlying all appearance (Book II).

Schopenhauer’s acceptance of Kant’s epistemological idealism combined with his non-rational ontological realism is, however, on display throughout The World as Will and Representation . Schopenhauer accepts without reservation Kant’s argument that space, time, and causality are forms of our own representation that we know a priori and impose upon the appearances of objects. He does precede this acceptance with a Fichtean argument that “The world is my representation”, where the sheer “mineness” of representation is supposed to be a “form…more universal than any other form,” including space, time, and causality ( WWR , §1, p. 23). Schopenhauer holds that “no truth is more certain, no truth is more independent of all others and no truth is less in need of proof than this one: that everything there is for cognition (i.e., the whole world) is only an object in relation to a subject, an intuition of a beholder ” ( WWR , §1, pp. 23–4). This simple and perhaps inescapable thought may be regarded as the most fundamental motivation for any form of epistemological idealism. On the basis of this proposition, Schopenhauer then tries to distinguish his position from what he takes to be the skepticism of Hume, that there is a real question about whether there is either a subject or an object in addition to representations, and from the dogmatism of Fichte, that both of these can be proved; his own view as initially stated is rather that “the object as such always presupposes the subject as its necessary correlate: so the subject always remains outside the jurisdiction of the principle of sufficient reason” ( WWR , §5, p. 35). But, speaking of dogmatism, he simply accepts from Kant that “space and time can not only be conceived abstractly, on their own and independently of their content, but they can also be intuited immediately”, and that “This intuition is not some phantasm derived from repeated experience; rather, it is something independent of experience, and to such an extent that experience must in fact be conceived as dependent on it, since the properties of time and space, as they are known a priori in intuition, apply to all experience as laws that it must always come out in accordance with” ( WWR , §3, p. 27). By this remark, Schopenhauer indicates his recognition that Kant derives his epistemological idealism from his understanding of the implications of our a priori cognition of space and time, but he does not attempt to explain Kant’s inference or to add any argument of his own. Schopenhauer also does not doubt that there is something other than the representing subject beyond what it represents, an underlying reality beginning with its own body as it is rather than as it merely appears.

Schopenhauer’s fundamental departure from Kant is already suggested in this passage: “We have immediate cognition of the thing in itself when it appears to us as our own body; but our cognition is only indirect when the thing in itself is objectified in other objects of intuition” ( WWR , §6, pp. 40–1). What Schopenhauer means is that although we have an experience of our own bodies, as it were from the outside, through the same forms of space, time, and causality through which we experience all other bodies, including other animate bodies, and in this regard we experience all bodies including our own as mere appearance through the forms we impose on experience, we also have another experience, each of us of his or her own body, as it were from the inside, namely we have an experience of willing an action and of our bodies as the instruments of our wills, with no separation between will and action and thus no relevance of spatial separation, temporal succession, or difference between cause and effect. However—and this is the argument of Book II—our immediate experience of our own bodies as instruments of our wills is an experience of our actions being immediately determined by desire rather than by reason. “To the pure subject of cognition as such, [his] body is a representation like any other among objects,” but “ will …and this alone gives him the key to his own appearance, reveals to him the meaning and shows him the inner workings of his essence, his deeds, his movements” ( WWR , §18, p. 124); and what we discover when we look closely at our wills is that they are governed not by reason but by impulse, at its most fundamental level a “dark, dull driving” ( WWR , §27, p. 174), and even at its highest, most clarified level, still desires or apparently “creative drives” that only “seem to perform their tasks from abstract, rational motives” ( WWR , §27, p. 182). It is not our planning and calculating drives that best express the real nature of the will but our genitals ( WWR , §20, p. 133). Of course, it is well known that following the lead of one’s genitals is a pretty good formula for disappointment, and for Schopenhauer this reveals the frustration to which a will driven by desire ultimately leads: either one does not get what one wants, the object of one’s desire, and is frustrated, or one does, but then one wants more, and either does not get that, so is frustrated, or does, but then wants more, and so on ad infinitum . Trying to truly satisfy desire is the height of irrationality, but for Schopenhauer there is nothing else we can will—we can at best try to escape from the clutches of will altogether, whether through art, asceticism, or compassion.

But of course, if the underlying nature of reality, the thing in itself, is nothing other than will, than escape from its clutches should not really be possible but should at most be apparent. And not only does Schopenhauer equate our experience of ourselves “from the inside” as desire-driven will with our own ultimate reality, our character as things in themselves; he also argues that we have no choice but to think of the underlying reality of all appearance in this way, because this is our only form of insight into—or acquaintance with—anything as a thing in itself. We can only “take the key to the understanding of the essence in itself of things” to be the “key provided…by the immediate cognition of our own essence, and apply it to [the] appearances in the inorganic [and organic] world as well,” even appearances that are more remote from us than any others. Ultimate reality, because, Schopenhauer assumes, “it is everywhere one and the same,…must be called will here as well as there, a name signifying the being in itself of every thing in the world and the sole kernel of every appearance” ( WWR , §23, pp. 142–3). Schopenhauer devotes many pages to empirical descriptions of the similarities between the forces at work throughout the rest of nature and the merely apparently rational but really non-rational character of our own behavior, but of course the character of things in themselves cannot be inferred directly from any amount of empirical data; Schopenhauer derives his conclusion not from all this empirical illustration but rather from our allegedly immediate rather than empirical insight into the character of our own wills and the very problematic premise that at bottom everything is essentially one.

It may seem far-fetched to think of Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) as an idealist. After all, he presented himself as an almost fanatical anti-idealist throughout his life. In many of his published and unpublished writings as well as in his letters he expresses over and again his dislike and his disdain for what he calls “idealism.” A telling summary of his position concerning idealism is to be found in his letter to Malvida von Meysenburg (October 20, 1888): “and I treat idealism as untruthfulness that has become an instinct, a not-wanting-to-see reality at any price: every sentence of my writings contains contempt for idealism ”. This harsh assessment is by no means easy to understand given his known sympathies with a perspectival approach to objects of cognition, his insistence that falsification or tampering ( Verfälschung ) is at the basis of most of our cognitive judgments, and his claims as to the dependence of knowledge on needs. Considerations like these suggest that in spite of his protests, idealistic modes of thinking are not alien to Nietzsche. At least some of his beliefs are compatible with what has been called here epistemological idealism although Nietzsche himself would have taken these beliefs to express a form of realism. However, before searching for and elaborating on possible idealistic tendencies in his own thoughts, we should find out what “idealism” meant for Nietzsche and why he was so hostile to it.

Idealism, for Nietzsche, seems to be a particularly unappealing form of metaphysics, and this means philosophy as it has been practiced throughout history from the era of the ancient Greeks up to his own time (because of his contempt for Kant’s postulate s of pure practical reason, Nietzsche gave little credence to Kant’s theoretical critique of traditional metaphysics). Philosophy in this traditional shape he took to be a somewhat enigmatic endeavor to pursue the mutually excluding tasks of (culture-forming) art and religion on the one hand and of (cognition-focused) science on the other (s. Notebook 19, [47], [62], [218]; KSA 7. 434). It is doomed to failure because of two fundamental shortcomings. The first is that it gives a privileged status to truth in that it declares truth to be the ultimate goal at which it aims. This preoccupation with truth is based on the implicit assumption that truth has some overriding value. This assumption has never been justified, not even addressed by any philosopher. Nietzsche writes in the Genealogy of Morals (Section 24): “Turn to the most ancient and most modern philosophies: all of them lack a consciousness of the extent to which the will to truth itself needs a justification, here is a gap in every philosophy—where does it come from? Because the ascetic ideal has so far been lord over all philosophy, because truth was set as being, as god, as the highest authority itself, because truth was not allowed to be a problem. Do you understand this ‘allowed to be’?—From the very moment that faith in the God of the ascetic ideal is denied, there is a new problem as well : that of the value of truth.—The will to truth needs a critique—let us hereby define our own task—the value of truth is tentatively to be called into question ” ( KSA 5. 401; Third Essay). However, it is not the problem of the value of truth but the second shortcoming that, in Nietzsche’s eyes, leads directly to metaphysics. It is the tendency of philosophers to deny the obvious, to neglect surfaces in favor of what is allegedly behind them, out of habitual weakness and anxiety to prefer the stable and immutable over and against change and becoming. This critical sentiment Nietzsche expresses quite often at different places in many of his published and unpublished writings. A nice example is the following note: “On the psychology of metaphysics. This world is apparent—consequently there is a true world. This world is conditioned—consequently there is an unconditioned world. This world is full of contradiction—consequently there is a world free from contradiction. This world is becoming—consequently there is an existing [ seiende ] world. All false inferences (blind trust in reason: if A is, there must be its opposing concept B). It is suffering that inspires these inferences: at bottom there are wishes that such a world might be; similarly hatred of a world that causes suffering expresses itself through the imagination of another world, one full of value: the ressentiment of the metaphysicians against the actual world is here creative” (Notebook 8 [2]; KSA 12. 327) . This tendency to “falsify” ( verfälschen ) or to “re-evaluate/reframe” ( umdeuten ) reality out of resentment is, according to Nietzsche, especially well documented in the idealistic tradition in metaphysics, as is shown paradigmatically in Plato’s idealism. It was Plato who invented the idea of another world that is much more real, much more true than the ever changing, always instable world in which we live; he invented the fiction of the supreme reality of an imperishable and everlasting ideal world inhabited by archetypal ideas and immutable forms, a “world in itself” in comparison to which the “ Lebenswelt ” of everyday experience is just a pale shadow. Yet Nietzsche seems undecided how to evaluate the real motives that led Plato to his idealism. Sometimes he wants to distinguish Plato from other idealists by crediting him with some obscure positive reason for endorsing idealism. In section 372 of The Gay Science , entitled precisely “ Why we are not idealists ,” he writes: “In sum: all philosophical idealism until now was something like an illness, except where, as in the case of Plato, it was the caution of an overabundant and dangerous health, the fear of overpowerful senses, the shrewdness of a shrewd Socratic” ( KSA 3. 623). However, there are other passages where Nietzsche is not in such a charitable mood and where he presents the ultimate reasons for Plato’s strong leanings towards idealism as rooted in weakness and resentment as is the case with all the other idealists in the history of philosophy (e.g. Ecce Homo . 3. KSA 6. 311). His ultimate verdict on metaphysics in all its ancient and modern forms is nicely expressed in the following note: “On the psychology of metaphysics. The influence of fearfulness. What has been most feared, the cause of the most powerful suffering (the lust for domination, sexual lust, etc.) has been treated by humans most hostile and eliminated from the ‘true’ world. Thus they have step by step wiped out the affects—claimed God to be the opposite of the evil, i.e., reality to consist in the negation of desires and affects (which is to say precisely in nothingness). Likewise they hate the irrational, the arbitrary, the accidental (as the cause of countless physical suffering). Consequently they negate this element in that-which-is-in-itself, they conceive it as absolute ‘rationality’ and ‘purposiveness.’ In the same way they fear change, transitoriness: therein is expressed an oppressed soul, full of mistrust and bad experience (The case of Spinoza: an inverted sort of person would count this change as charming). A playful being overladen with power would call precisely the affects, unreason and change good in an eudaimonistic sense, together with their consequences, with danger, contrast, dissolution, etc.” ( KSA 13. 536).

However, this thoroughly critical assessment of all forms of idealisms as abominable expressions of intellectual weakness and vindictiveness seems to be at odds with another of Nietzsche’s cherished beliefs, according to which we have to take reality to be not only dependent on but ultimately constituted by the respective perspectives on or the respective ways of interpreting what we encounter. This Nietzschean view can give rise to the impression that in the end he might have been closer to endorsing some form of epistemological idealism, maybe even some form of metaphysical idealism as he himself realizes. This leads to the topics of perspectivism and interpretation ( Auslegung ) in Nietzsche.

Although the details are far from clear, the general tendency of his perspectivism is expressed quite well in aphorism 374 from The Gay Science : “How far the perspectival character of existence extends, indeed whether it has any other character; whether an existence without interpretation, without ‘sense,’ does not become ‘non-sense’; whether, on the other hand, all existence is not essentially an interpreting existence—that cannot be decided, as would be fair, even by the most studious and scrupulous analysis and self- examination of the intellect; for in the course of this analysis, the human intellect cannot avoid seeing itself under its perspectival forms, and solely in these.…Rather, the world has once again become infinite to us: insofar as we cannot reject the possibility that it includes infinite interpretations ” ( KSA 3. 626). This view, according to which, further, the world each of us is experiencing is the product of an interpretation forced on us by some unconscious overriding drive ( Trieb ) that is the formative mark of the individual character of each of us, might be seen as endorsing a version of epistemological idealism if, as it is here, epistemological idealism is understood as the claim that what appears to be known as it is independent of the mind is in the end inescapably marked by the creative, formative, constructive activities of human mind, whether individual or collective. However, it is far from clear whether Nietzsche wants us to think of this process of interpretation which leads to a specific perspective as a mind-dependent activity. Sometimes it seems as if he is favoring a quasi-Humean view according to which the intellect operates in the service of some anonymous affective and emotional drives in such a way that it just provides a set of necessary means to consciously realize what drives force us to do. The following note, for example, points in this direction: “Against positivism, which would stand by the position ‘There are only facts,’ I would say: no, there are precisely no facts, only interpretations. We can establish no fact ‘in itself’: it is perhaps nonsense to want such a thing. You say ‘Everything is subjective’: but that is already an interpretation, the ‘subject’ is not anything given, but something invented and added, something stuck behind…To the extent that the word ‘knowledge’ [ Erkenntnis ] has any sense, the world is knowable: but it is interpretable differently, it has no sense behind it, but innumerable senses, ‘perspectivism.’ It is our needs that interpret the world: our drives and their to and fro. Every drive is a kind of domination, every one has its perspective, which it would force on all other drives as a norm” (Notebook 7 [60]. KSA 12. 315). In other passages Nietzsche seems to be more in line with a by and large Kantian view according to which the intellect provides some rules of transformation of what is given by the senses as individual and discrete data into more general representations. Thus we find him claiming in section 354 of The Gay Science : “This is what I understand to be true phenomenalism and perspectivism: that due to the nature of animal consciousness , the world of which we can become conscious is merely a surface- and sign-world, a world turned into generalities and thereby debased to its lowest common denominator,—that everything that enters consciousness thereby becomes superficial, thin, relatively stupid, general, a sign, a mark of the herd, that all becoming-conscious involves a vast and fundamental corruption, falsification, superficialization, and generalization” ( KSA 3. 593). Be this as it may, at least as far as epistemological idealism is concerned it is by no means obvious that either his explicit criticism of idealism or his remarks on the ways we make up epistemic worlds prevent Nietzsche from coming close to an idealist position himself. This is so because in epistemology his main enemy does not seem to be idealism but all forms of realism.

Although his proximity to epistemological idealism does not directly imply any ontological claims, one could be tempted to see Nietzsche as toying with some ontologically idealistic fantasies. His speculations concerning the will to power as the ultimate dynamic foundation of all reality fall into this category. For example, “Perspectivism is only a complex form of specificity[.] My idea is, that every specific body strives to become lord over all of space and to expand its force (—its will to power) and to repel everything that resists its own expansion. But it perpetually collides with the equal efforts of other bodies, and ends by making an arrangement (‘unifying’) with those that are closely enough related to it:—thus they conspire together to power. And the process goes on…” (Notebook 14 [186]. KSA 13. 373 f.). This idea of conspiring forces as the supreme world-constituting entities can look like an allusion to Kant’s physics of attraction and repulsion, but also to a version of ontological idealism like those of Fichte and Schelling because it too invites us to conceive of dynamic processes as ontologically prior to (physical or mental) objects and events. Thus, in the end there are no real obstacles to thinking of Nietzsche as an ontological as well as epistemological idealist, although the speculations that lead him in the former direction may be separable from the latter.

Interest in ontological idealism waned in Germany in the second half of the nineteenth century and the first decades of the twentieth, although it remained lively in other parts of Europe (for example, in Italy, in the person of Benedetto Croce). This had to do on the one hand with a certain aversion against what was taken to be an excessive and extravagant usurpation of all fields of intellectual discourse by the classical German philosophers under the pretext of idealism and on the other hand with the rise of Neo-Kantianism which also at least partly came into being as a reaction against the German idealists, although insofar as Neo-Kantianism was a reaction to absolute idealism it could not entirely reject epistemological idealism. Things were different in the English-speaking world, where idealism became an important topic in a wide spectrum of philosophical discussions ranging from metaphysics via aesthetics to moral and social theories. In philosophical Britain, that is to say, England and Scotland, an idealism that was ultimately both epistemological and ontological became the dominant approach to philosophy for several decades, while in the United States idealism could not monopolize philosophy, having to share the stage with and ultimately reach an accommodation with pragmatism, but it nevertheless also flourished for several decades. The best known and most outspoken spokesmen in favor of idealistic conceptions in metaphysics and elsewhere in Britain in these years were T.H. Green and F. H. Bradley at Oxford and J. McT. E. McTaggart at Cambridge, while in the United States the most prominent idealist was Josiah Royce at Harvard (where idealism’s having to share the stage with pragmatism was personified in Royce’s friendly rivalry with William James). Although all of these figures are frequently characterized as being indebted to Hegel’s writings and advocating a Hegelian view of reality, their various positions are at best in a somewhat indirect, almost only metaphorical, sense informed by Hegel’s philosophy. In fact, these philosophers were more willing to call themselves idealists than had been the earlier German idealists who supposedly inspired them, but who as has been argued were just as interested in escaping as in accepting the label. This is shown most tellingly insofar as their approach to a defense of idealism goes back to a state of the discussion characteristic of the period prior to Hegel and German idealism in general, rather connecting more directly to an understanding of idealism influenced by eighteenth-century disputes in the wake of Berkeley. None of these figures except perhaps Royce continued to explore a dynamic conception of idealism distinctive of Hegel and the other German idealists—Royce in fact wrote more extensively and insightfully on Hegel and his immediate predecessors than any of the others. In general, the late nineteenth-century idealists were more inclined to think of idealism or, maybe more accurately, spiritualism again as a genuine alternative to materialism and embark again on the controversy whether matter or mind/spirit is the ultimate “stuff” of reality. These philosophers were thus more willing to identify themselves as ontological idealists than had been their predecessors; our opening definition of ontological idealism from Royce may be seen as coming from this background. However, these philosophers were not all equally monists. Both Bradley and McTaggart, for whom a defense of idealism consists mainly in establishing the ontological point that reality is exclusively spirit, were, and thus their idealism could also be called “spiritual monism.” But both Green at the beginning of the movement and Royce towards its end strove for more nuanced positions, not excluding the existence of matter from their idealisms, and thus resisted monism. But all their efforts to establish a convincing form of idealism, whether in the form of spiritualism or in a form that allowed some role for matter as well, became rapidly unfashionable even during the lifetimes of all these philosophers (except for Green, who died young) due to what was called “the revolt against idealism” staged at the turn of the twentieth century in Britain by Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore and a decade later in the United States by a group of “New Realists.” However, as we will suggest in our concluding comments at least Russell was himself pushed back in the direction of some form of idealism, perhaps only epistemological idealism, by the time his own thought reached the stage of his “logical atomism.” It might even be suggested that Ludwig Wittgenstein’s own movement from the early logical realism of his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus to the meaning-as-use theory of the Philosophical Investigations is itself a movement towards a form of epistemological idealism. And it might further be suggested that a wide variety of other paradigmatic analytic philosophers, such as Rudolf Carnap and even nominalists such as Nelson Goodman and W.V. Quine, incorporated some aspects of epistemological idealism into their thought. Although the name “idealism” became anathema after the revolt of Russell, Moore, and the New Realists, the substance of at least epistemological idealism may have lived on.

Thomas Hill Green (1836–82) was the first of the great Oxford idealists. He is best remembered for a lengthy polemic with Hume that he published in the form of an introduction to a collected edition of Hume that he co-edited and for his posthumously published Prolegomena to Ethics , which is a polemic against utilitarianism from the point of view of a perfectionism inspired by Kant as well as by Hegel. But the first of the four books of the Prolegomena is a “Metaphysics of Knowledge,” beginning with a statement of “The Spiritual Principle in Knowledge and in Nature,” which argues for a form of idealism both epistemological and ontological, and Green’s posthumous works also included a set of lectures on Kant in which he engaged quite directly with Kant’s form of idealism. Green also left behind a set of Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation that form one of the crucial documents of the political and social philosophy of British idealism and of idealism in the broadest sense mentioned at the outset of this entry.

Green’s motivation in arguing for idealism in the Prolegomena is to prepare the way for a conception of the will as free and creative as the foundation of his ethics. Green’s idealism is expounded in three main steps. First, and here much influenced by Kant, he argues that knowledge never consists in the mere apprehension of discrete items, but in the recognition of order or relation, and that such order or relation is not given but is constituted by and in consciousness. Thus, “The terms ‘real’ and ‘objective’…have no meaning except for a consciousness which presents its experiences to itself as determined by relations, and at the same time conceives a single and unalterable order of relations determining them, with which its temporary presentation, as each experience occurs, of the relations determining it may be contrasted” ( Prolegomena , p. 17). From this he infers that “experience, in the sense of a consciousness of events as a related series—and in no other sense can it help to account for the knowledge of an order of nature—cannot be explained by any natural history, properly so called” (p. 22), but must instead be constituted by mind itself, or, “the understanding which presents an order of nature to us is in principle one with an understanding which constitutes that order itself” (p. 24). Thus far, Green’s position could be considered epistemological idealism. However, he quickly moves beyond merely epistemological idealism, because his next move is to argue that since the order of which any individual human being is in various ways and to various degrees aware obviously extends beyond what could plausibly be thought to be constituted just by that individual, the order of which we are each aware must be constituted by a mind or intelligence greater than that of any of us, thus there must be “an eternal intelligence realized in the related facts of the world,” and the world must be “a system of related facts rendered possible by such an intelligence,” which intelligence “partially and gradually reproduces itself in us, communicating piece-meal but in inseparable correlation” aspects of that order to each of us if not complete knowledge of it to any of us (p. 41). Green’s insistence on a supra-individual intelligence as the source of cosmic order in which individual intelligences in some way participate is a decided move beyond merely epistemological idealism, and in his own view it is also a significant departure from Kant, whose agnosticism about the real nature of things in themselves, at least in the theoretical mood, “would at once withhold us” from such an inference to the “spirituality of the real world” (43). However, and here is the third main thesis of Green’s form of idealism, the participation of individual human beings in the supra-individual intelligence which constitutes the comprehensive system of relations can be seen as an apprehension of some portion of that order by animal organisms : “in the growth of our experience, in the process of our learning to know the world, an animal organism, which has its history in time, gradually becomes the vehicle of an eternally complete consciousness” (p. 77); it is the eternal consciousness, “as so far realized in or communicated to us through modification of the animal organism, that constitutes our knowledge, with the relations, characteristic of knowledge, into which time does not enter, which are not in becoming but are once for all what they are” (p. 78). Green’s form of spiritualism is thus not incompatible with ontological dualism: the object of all knowledge is the complete and eternal order of things, which must be constituted by an intelligence greater than that of any individual human being, but individual human beings are in fact organisms, thus matter, to which some aspect of that intelligence is communicated. Green’s epistemological idealism is complete, because knowledge on the part of an individual is understood as consisting in a grasp of an order that is itself mental, but his ontological idealism is not exclusive, that is, it includes the necessary existence of a supra-individual intelligence or spirit but allows the existence of animal organisms (and thus presumably of other forms of matter as well).

Francis Herbert Bradley (1846–1924), however, argued for a more exclusive spiritualism, or ontological idealism. Bradley presents his metaphysical views on the constitution and the main characteristics of reality most explicitly in Appearance and Reality: A Metaphysical Essay, which was first published in 1893 and reprinted many times during his lifetime. He famously proceeds from the claim that the traditional and received “ideas by which we try to understand the universe” are contradictory (11). He substantiates this claim by examining a range of central concepts from metaphysics and epistemology, among them the concepts of primary and secondary qualities, of substance and attribute, of quality and relation, space and time, of causality as well as the concept of a thing and that of the self. The result of this examination consists in the verdict that all attempts to capture the true nature of reality in terms of these categories are futile because all these concepts are unintelligible, inconsistent and in the end self-contradictory. This means that what is designated by means of them cannot be real, but can only reflect the way the world appears to us, not the way it really is. This diagnosis is based on Bradley’s fundamental conviction that “ultimate reality is such that it does not contradict itself” (136). He takes this to be “an absolute criterion” (ibid.). However, to be just appearance is not to be unreal in the sense of an illusion. On the contrary, although appearance is “inconsistent with itself”, one cannot deny its existence or “divorce it from reality” because “reality, set on one side and apart from all appearance, would assuredly be nothing” (132).

Yet since appearance always proves to be an inadequate way in which reality is present to us, the question inevitably arises whether it is beyond our means ever to become acquainted with the true essence of ultimate reality or whether we can avoid skepticism and claim that it is indeed possible for us to have access to the constitutive nature of reality. Bradley emphatically endorses the latter possibility. According to him, the self-contradictoriness of what is appearance already implies that there is positive knowledge of reality: reality has to be One in the sense that it does not allow discord and it must be such that it can include diversity (cf. 140, 144), i.e. “the Absolute is … an individual and a system” (144). This character of reality as an internally diversified individual system is revealed to us in sentient experience. “Sentient experience … is reality, and what is not this is not real” (ibid.). According to Bradley it is this sentient experience that “is commonly called psychical existence” (ibid.). The material basis of sentient experience is exhausted in feeling, thought, and volition. Thus reality consists in what has to be taken as the undifferentiated unity of these modes of sentient experience before these modes make their appearance as different aspects of experience. This leads Bradley to assume that what is ultimately real is just what gives rise to appearances where appearances have to be understood as specific forms under which the underlying undifferentiated unity appears in each of these different aspects of experience. In his words: “… there is no way of qualifying the Real except by appearances, and outside the Real there remains no space in which appearances could live” (551). Although he concedes “our complete inability to understand this concrete unity in detail” he insists that this inability “is no good ground for our declining to entertain it” (160). And although he claims at the end of his metaphysical essay that he does not know whether his “conclusions” are to be called Realism or Idealism (547), at the very end he nevertheless abruptly states: “We may fairly close this work then by insisting that Reality is spiritual” (552). This might lead us to assume that, “in the end” (a favorite phrase of Bradley’s), it was primarily his search for a basis for spiritualism and not so much a defense of idealism understood as opposed to realism that motivated him to explore the true nature of reality; in other words, he was ultimately driven by an impulse toward ontological idealism even though he had developed powerful arguments for a form of epistemological idealism.

The identification of idealism with spiritualism, thus again an ontological interpretation of idealism, is most explicit in the works of John McTaggart Ellis McTaggart (1866–1925). His very first published writing (“The Further Determination of the Absolute”) starts with the following proclamation: “The progress of an idealistic philosophy may, from some points of view, be divided into three stages. The problem of the first is to prove that reality is not exclusively matter. The problem of the second is to prove that reality is exclusively spirit. The problem of the third is to determine what is the fundamental nature of spirit” (In: Philosophical Studies , pp. 210 f.). And the last of his writings published in his life time (“An Ontological Idealism”) starts with the confession, explicitly employing the same terminology that we have used here: “Ontologically I am an Idealist, since I believe that all that exists is spiritual” (ibid., 273). He takes spirit to be the sum total of individual spirits or selves connected by the relation of love and bases this conviction on the claim that only this conception of what ultimate reality consists in allows us to overcome unavoidable contradictions connected with all other attempts to reconcile unity and diversity as the distinguishing marks of reality. Harmony between unity and diversity can be established only on the basis of an all-encompassing relation of love between all the characteristic elements of reality, which in turn presupposes thinking of ultimate reality as a community of spirits or as Spirit. These—as McTaggart himself admits (ibid. 271 f.)—rather mystical-sounding assertions, which he adhered to all his life, he tries to back up by a number of different considerations. In his earliest writing he relies heavily on views held by Bradley to the effect that we have to accept that contradictions are a criterion for non-reality. However, he does not employ this criterion as a logical maxim but transforms it into some kind of ontological principle according to which everything that prevents harmony cannot be real. In his last work, his attempt to present an argument for his ontological idealism is based mainly on (1) mereological considerations concerning the structure of substances which aim to show that only spirits can claim the status of a substance, and on (2) his theory of time, the unreality of which he famously had proven in his magnum opus The Nature of Existence (1921/27). It is interesting to note that McTaggart does not believe that his metaphysical (ontological) spiritual idealism excludes a realistic stance in epistemology. On the contrary, he declares himself an “epistemological realist” (ibid., 273). This is so because he characterizes epistemological realism as a position that is based on a correspondence theory of truth according to which a belief is true if it corresponds to a fact. Because everything that is real is a fact and (according to McTaggart) nothing is unreal (although it may not exist), all beliefs about something are beliefs about facts and consequently about something that is epistemologically real. Although this concept of epistemological realism is vague, it suggests that McTaggart thought of idealism not primarily in opposition to realism but much more in terms of a doctrine that is opposed to materialism, that is, as an ontological rather than epistemological doctrine. But his insistence that his view is a form of realism may be taken as an extreme form of the usual distinction between epistemological idealism and any view that our knowledge is merely illusory, an aspect of epistemological idealism that goes back to Berkeley and Kant (although Kant thought that Berkeley had failed to establish it).

Idealism was also a prominent mode of philosophy in the United States during the late nineteenth century, alongside pragmatism, but while pragmatism remained prominent throughout the twentieth century, whether under that name or not, the reputation of idealism was permanently damaged by a movement toward “realism” early in the century (which also attacked pragmatism, although without the same effect). Earlier in the nineteenth century, the popular essayist Ralph Waldo Emerson, the most philosophical of the New England “Transcendentalists,” had struck many idealist themes, and after the Civil War a school of “St. Louis Hegelians” emerged, whose efforts were primarily exegetical. But the leading American idealist was Josiah Royce (1855–1916). Deeply influenced by Charles Sanders Peirce, particularly the lectures that Peirce gave in Cambridge in 1898, Royce incorporated aspects of Peirce’s pragmatism into his version of idealism, giving an idealist spin to Peirce’s conception of truth as what would be known at the end of inquiry were that ever to be reached. But Royce’s argument always remained that epistemological idealism must ultimately lead to ontological or as he called it metaphysical idealism.

A prolific author who published fifteen books before his early death at sixty, Royce launched his defense of idealism in his first book, The Religious Aspect of Philosophy (1885). In this work he introduced his first novel argument, for idealism, what he called the argument from error. Royce’s claim is that skepticism begins with insistence upon the possibility of error, but that recognition of that possibility presupposes not just that there is “absolute truth” (p. 385) but that in some sense we have to know that absolute truth, or at least some aspect of it, in order to have an object even for our erroneous claims, thus that we must have some access to a “higher inclusive thought” even to make an erroneous knowledge claim. In his words, “Either then there is no error, or else judgments are true and false only in reference to a higher inclusive thought, which they presuppose, and which must, in the last analysis, be assumed as Infinite and all-inclusive” (p. 393). Royce holds that we must have some sort of apprehension of the “higher inclusive thought” in order to be able even to make our errors, and then that the growth of human knowledge over time consists in increasing apprehension of this all-inclusive truth without any limit being prescribed by our subordinate status. This is the epistemological optimism that pervades all Royce’s work and his subsequent debate with Bradley.

This account does not yet make clear why Royce thought that epistemological idealism must lead to ontological idealism; that becomes clearer in his subsequent works. Royce’s next major statement of his idealism came in The Spirit of Modern Philosophy (1892). The second part of the book more fully develops Royce’s own arguments for idealism. Here Royce gives a clear definition of his conception of idealism and adds to the previous argument from error a second argument, from meaning. The core of this argument is that the intended object of an expression or thought must itself be conceived or understood in some way, so that we always mean what are in some sense our own ideas, although of course at any particular moment we hardly know or understand everything about the object to which we refer; that is why the idea that is the ultimate object of reference may be much greater than the idea that refers. In Royce’s words, “The self that is doubting or asserting, or that is even feeling its private ignorance about an object, and that still, even in consequence of all this, is meaning , is aiming at such an object, is in essence identical with the self for which this object exists in its complete and consciously known truth” ( Spirit of Modern Philosophy , pp. 370–1). By means of this argument, any restriction of Royce’s position to a purely epistemological idealism is eliminated: the possibility of meaning requires an identity between what means and what is meant, and since anything might be meant, anything at all must in some way be identical with what means, subjects and their ideas and expressions, even though that identity can hardly be absolute, and the ordinary conscious subject may seem very different and more limited than the “ one Self” (p. 373) that underlies the appearances of both ordinary subjects and ordinary objects.

Royce develops an even more systematic argument for an idealism that is both epistemological and ontological in his magnum opus , the two volumes of his 1899–1900 Gifford lectures published as The World and the Individual —as the title suggests, a major theme of that work is explicating in detail the relationship between underlying reality and ordinary individual, conscious human selves. In this book, Royce expounds his idealism as the last of the four possible “conceptions of being.” The first is the “realistic conception of Being,” which is defined by the conception of being as completely independent of thought, so that whatever is true of it is true quite independently of what may be thought about it. The second conception of being is the mystical conception. As the defining notion of the realist conception was independence, the defining notion of mysticism is the opposite, namely immediacy, the idea that thought and its object must be one. The third conception of being, which Royce sometimes calls the theory of “validity,” is that “To be real now means, primarily, to be valid, to be true, to be in essence the standard for ideas ” (I:202). This conception of being tries to retain realism’s recognition of independence through the thought that “some of my ideas are already, and apart from my private experience, valid, true, well-grounded” (I:204) and mysticism’s identification of subject and object through the thought that reality is itself possible experience, but adds structure to the now unified realms of thought and being instead of eliminating structure.

The fourth conception of being is a fuller development of the conception of meaning that Royce had introduced in The Spirit of Modern Philosophy . He now links meaning to purpose, and his thought is that the meaning of a term is an intended purpose, a problem to be solved, for example a mathematical problem to be solved or object to be constructed, and that in using a term the user already has some approach to solving the problem in mind but the full solution remains to be developed, may never be fully developed in the life of a particular individual, but is in some sense already included in the larger thought that constitutes reality. Reaching back to both Hegel and Kant, Royce conceives of the progress of knowledge as making the meaning of our ideas more determinate. In this he is also influenced by Peirce, and his notion of meaning is clearly a version of Peirce’s approach to truth, on which a proposition is true if it would be affirmed at the final stage of human inquiry, with the difference that while for Peirce the final stage of human enquiry is essentially a regulative ideal without ontological commitment, for Royce, the comprehensive meaning in which all ideas would be fully determinate is actually thought, although by a sort of super-self, not by any particular finite human self or even by all the selves thinking at any one time. Royce makes the transition from thought to being by stating that “In its wholeness the world of Being is the world of individually expressed meanings, an individual life, consisting of the individual embodiments of the wills represented by all finite ideas” (I:341–2).

Royce’s arguments for idealism collectively, which in many ways return to the basic form of modern idealism pioneered by Green, whose Prolegomena had been published just a couple of years before Royce’s own career began, illustrate the pressure that often forced a move from epistemological to ontological idealism. Epistemological idealism begins with the insight that our knowledge in some way or another always reflects the structure of our own consciousness and thought. But the difference between what any particular individual believes or even knows at any particular time and what may be true and be known as a whole, at a time or over time, is too great to ignore, and must be modeled within epistemological idealism. But once it has been assumed that thought or mind itself is the proper object of knowledge, the only way to do this is to make a contrast between individual thought and some sort of supra-individual thought. At the outset of modern idealism, in Berkeley, that takes the form of the infinite mind, God, contrasted to individual, human minds; in later forms, such as those of Green and Royce, the supra-individual mind is not always identified with God, but plays the same role. In the cases of both Green and Royce, the union of epistemological and ontological idealism also provided the basis for a moral idealism based on an insistence upon the underlying commonality of individual human selves in the larger self that Royce called the Absolute. But we will not be able to trace that line of thought here, and will instead conclude with the suggestion that many subsequent philosophers drew back from the full-blooded combination of epistemological and ontological idealism offered by Green, Bradley, McTaggart, and Royce to what was ultimately a more purely epistemological form of idealism. This might seem a surprising claim, since the immediate response both to the British idealists and to Royce in the U.S. came from philosophers who identified themselves as realists. Nevertheless, it might be argued that even after it lost the dignity of appearing under its own name, epistemological idealism remained a dominant mode of philosophy in the twentieth century, even if not especially within analytic philosophy, although not many of its practitioners would have admitted that. A case in point would be Bertrand Russell.

Both epistemological and ontological idealism came under massive attack in Britain at the turn of the twentieth century by George Edward Moore (1873–1958) and Bertrand Russell (1872–1970), while in the United States Royce’s position was attacked by a school of younger “New Realists,” to some extent inspired by his life-long interlocutor William James, who included E.B. Holt and his younger Harvard colleague Ralph Barton Perry, and later Roy Wood Sellars (the father of Wilfrid Sellars, who later moved back to a form of Kantianism, and thus became one of the leading crypto-epistemological idealists of the twentieth century), and Arthur Lovejoy. But both Moore and Russell had more of an enduring influence on the course of analytic philosophy than the American New Realists, but also reveal the continuing impulse to idealism in spite of their own efforts, so we will focus on them. Both of them take idealism to be spiritualism in the spirit of Berkeley and Bradley (neither of them mentions their Cambridge tutor McTaggart!), i.e., they think of idealism as a position which is characterized by the claim that the universe (Moore) or whatever exists or whatever can be known to exist (Russell) is spiritual (Moore) or in some sense mental (Russell). Although their attack was so influential that even more than 100 years later, any acknowledgment of idealistic tendencies is viewed in the English-speaking world with reservation, it is by no means obvious that they actually thought they had disproved idealism. On the contrary, neither Moore nor Russell claimed to have demonstrated that the universe or what exists or can be known to exist is not spiritual or mental. All that they take themselves to have shown is that there are no good philosophical (in contradistinction to, e.g., theological or psychological) arguments available to support such a claim. Moore especially is very explicit about this point. He devotes the first five pages of his famous piece from 1903, “The Refutation of Idealism,” to assuring the reader over and over that “I do not suppose that anything I shall say has the smallest tendency to prove that reality is not spiritual. … Reality may be spiritual, for all I know; and I devoutly hope it is. … It is, therefore, only with idealistic arguments that I am concerned; … I shall have proved that Idealists have no reason whatever for their conclusion” ( Philosophical Studies , pp. 2 f.). And Russell in his The Problems of Philosophy (1912), in a similar vein, warns the reader, after emphasizing the strangeness of an idealistic position from a common sense point of view: “[I]f there were good reasons to regard them [viz. physical objects] as mental, we could not legitimately reject this opinion merely because it strikes us as strange” (p. 38).

Moore and Russell found two main arguments for idealism to be fallacious. The first concerns Berkeley’s idealistic principle that being consists in being perceived, the second the converse claim, attributed to Bradley, that thought entails being. Their criticism of the first as well as their rebuttal of the second argument stems from certain convictions they share as to the nature of knowledge, and is meant to discredit both epistemological and ontological idealism. The assault on Berkeley is staged by Moore most extensively in “The Refutation of Idealism” and picked up in an abbreviated form by Russell ten years later in the chapter on idealism in his The Problems of Philosophy , while the attack on Bradley, although foreshadowed in Russell’s Problems , is spelled out rather lengthily (and a bit nastily) by Moore in “The Conception of Reality” from 1917–18. Their main objection against the two idealistic arguments seems to be that they rely on unjustly presupposing that the mental act of relating to an object (perceiving, thinking, knowing, experiencing) is a necessary condition for the existence of this object. The fallacy involved here consists in failing to make “the distinction between act and object in our apprehending of things”, as Russell (ibid. 42) puts it, or, in Moore’s terminology of The Refutation , in wrongfully identifying the content of “consciousness” with its object (loc. cit., 19 ff.). As soon as this identification is given up and that distinction is made it is at least an open question whether things exist independently of the mind, and idealism insofar it neglects this distinction and holds fast to that identification is refuted because based on an invalid argument.

Whether this line of criticism of idealistic positions is indeed successful might be controversial, and even if it strikes home against Berkeley the charge that they simply conflate knowledge and object hardly seems to do justice to the elaborate arguments of the late nineteenth-century idealists. However, if one is convinced of the correctness of this criticism (as no doubt Moore and Russell were) then it makes way for interesting new perspectives in epistemology and metaphysics. This is so because if this criticism is taken to be successful it permits us to explore the possibility of a theory of knowledge that starts from the assumptions (a) that objects exist independently of us and (b) that to know an object means to be immediately related to the object as it is in itself (i.e., as it is undistorted by and independent from any mental activity). Both Moore and Russell can be understood to have embarked on this exploration in the course of which they came to conceive a position which is aptly called by Peter Hylton “Platonic Atomism” (“Idealism and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy”,p. 329).

The basic idea of this Platonic atomism seems to be the following: Knowledge consists in standing in an immediate relation to an independent individual object (assumption b). This immediate relation to individual objects is best known under Russell’s term “acquaintance.” If, by stipulation, knowledge is ultimately knowledge “by acquaintance,” then knowledge is restricted to knowledge of individual objects. Knowledge basically is knowledge of something or non-propositional knowledge. However, although this rather frugal conception of knowledge might be sufficient to give an account of the possibility of non-propositional knowledge, it is not that easy to see how such a conception can give a sensible explanation of propositional knowledge, i.e., of knowledge that something is so-and-so. Moore and Russell seem to have been acutely aware of this difficulty as is documented in their very explicit efforts to avoid it. It might have been their different reactions to this difficulty which in the years to come led them to proceed on diverging routes in philosophy. As is easy to imagine, there are two obvious reactions to the problem of propositional knowledge provided that assumption (b) is agreed upon. The first is to claim that propositions (Moore prefers the term “judgment” in this context) are individual objects with which the subject is acquainted (if he or she claims to know that something is so-and-so). The second is to broaden the concept of knowledge by not restricting knowledge to knowledge by acquaintance but to allow for other forms of knowledge as well. The first reaction apparently was the reaction of Moore and is formulated most prominently in his early piece “The Nature of Judgment” ( Mind , NS 8, 1899), while the second can be attributed to Russell and is documented most vividly in his The Problems of Philosophy .

According to Moore a proposition is composed out of concepts. If we are to be acquainted with propositions we have to take their elements, i.e., concepts, to have independent existence (because of assumption a). Moore points out: “… we have approached the nature of a proposition or judgment. A proposition is composed not of words, nor yet of thoughts, but of concepts. Concepts are possible objects of thought; but that is no definition of them. It merely states that they may come into relation with a thinker; and in order that they may do anything, they must already be something. It is indifferent to their nature whether anyone thinks them or not. They are incapable of change; and the relation into which they enter with the knowing subject implies no action or reaction. It is a unique relation which can begin to cease with a change in the subject; but the concept is neither cause nor effect of such a change. The occurrence of the relation has, no doubt, its causes and effects, but these are to be found only in the subject” (“The Nature of Judgment”, para. 9). Moore is well aware that this analysis of the nature of a proposition leads to some version of what could be called “conceptual realism,” according to which that what is “really” real are concepts because they are the ultimate objects of acquaintance. He explicitly states: “It would seem, in fact, …that a proposition is nothing other than a complex concept. The difference between a concept and a proposition, in virtue of which the latter alone can be called true or false, would seem to lie merely in the simplicity of the former. A proposition is a synthesis of concepts; and, just as concepts are themselves immutably what they are, so they stand in infinite relations to one another equally immutable. A proposition is constituted by any number of concepts, together with a specific relation between them; and according to the nature of this relation the proposition may be either true or false. What kind of relation makes a proposition true, what false, cannot be further defined, but must be immediately recognized” (ibid., para. 12). Moore also is very well aware that his view of the nature of concepts commits him to the claim that the world insofar as it is an object of propositional knowledge consists of concepts because these are the only things one can be acquainted with if acquaintance is a condition of knowledge. Thus he writes: “It seems necessary, then, to regard the world as formed of concepts. These are the only objects of knowledge. They cannot be regarded fundamentally as abstractions either from things or from ideas; since both alike can, if anything is to be true of them, composed of nothing but concepts. A thing becomes intelligible first when it is analyzed into its constituent concepts. The material diversity of things, which is generally taken as starting-point, is only derived; and the identity of the concept, in several different things, which appears on that assumption as the problem of philosophy, will now, if it instead be taken as the starting-point, render the derivation easy. Two things are then seen to be differentiated by the different relations in which their common concepts stand to other concepts. The opposition of concepts to existents disappears, since an existent is seen to be nothing but a concept or complex of concepts standing in a unique relation to the concept of existence” (ibid., para. 16).

Moore confesses that “I am fully aware of how paradoxical this theory must appear, and even how contemptible” (ibid., para. 14). And indeed one wonders whether such an account does not raise more problems than it answers. Fortunately we do not have to be concerned with this question here. However, if we ask whether Moore’s theory really manages to avoid idealism, it is hard not to conclude that its metaphysical commitments are precisely a form of ontological idealism, even if he has been led to his theory by an attempt to maintain epistemological realism! After all, to claim that only concepts are real, that they have a mode of being outside of space and time, that they are non-physical and completely unaffected by any activity of a thinking subject, does not sound very different from statements that can rightly be attributed to, e.g., Hegel, or even ultimately Plato, and that are meant to assert ontological idealism. The main difference in this case is that Moore’s conception of what a concept is has virtually nothing to do with what Hegel means by “concept,” but this does not suffice to establish ontological anti-idealism. Although Moore might avoid epistemological idealism by his insistence upon the metaphysical independence of concepts, he comes dangerously close to the point where the difference between ontological idealism and ontological realism vanishes and this distinction becomes a question of terminology.

Russell chooses a different path in the attempt to somehow reconcile the idea that knowledge has to be understood as a relation of acquaintance with objects with the phenomenon of propositional knowledge. He is more flexible both with respect to kinds of knowledge and with respect to kinds of objects with which we can be acquainted than Moore is. First of all, he distinguishes between knowledge of things and knowledge of truths. He recognizes two kinds of knowledge of things: knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Knowledge by acquaintance obtains whenever “we have acquaintance with anything of which we are directly aware, without the intermediary of any process of inference or any knowledge of truths” ( The Problems of Philosophy , 46). Knowledge by (definite) description obtains “when we know that it [i.e. the object] is ‘the so-and-so’, i.e. when we know that there is one object, and no more, having a certain property” (ibid., 53). The relation between these two kinds of knowledge is the following: “[K]nowledge concerning what is known by description is ultimately reducible to knowledge concerning what is known by acquaintance” (ibid., 58). Knowledge of truths is distinguished from these two kinds of knowledge of things . Knowledge of truths consists in pieces of knowledge that although they cannot be proven by experience are such that we nevertheless “see” their truth (ibid., 74). Examples of truths that can be known this way are logical principles, the principle of induction, and everything we know a priori . This taxonomy of kinds of knowledge, Russell believes, can account both for the possibility of non-propositional and propositional knowledge and at the same time retain the claim as to the primacy of the acquaintance-relation for knowledge.

The obvious question now is: if all knowledge is ultimately based on acquaintance, what is it we can be acquainted with, i.e. what are the legitimate objects of acquaintance? Because, according to Russell, the acquaintance relation is a relation to individual things this question translates into “what are the individual things we can be acquainted with?” Russell’s answer to this question is that there are exactly two kinds of things we can be acquainted with, namely particulars, i.e., things that exist, and universals, i.e., things that subsist (cf. ibid., 100). Particulars comprise sense-data, thoughts, feelings, desires and memories of “things which have been data either of the outer senses or of the inner sense” (ibid., 51). Universals are “opposed to the particular things that are given in sensation. We speak of whatever is given in sensation, or is of the same nature as things given in sensation, as a particular ; by opposition to this, a universal will be anything which may be shared by many particulars” (ibid., 93). Universals are conceptual entities: “These entities are such as can be named by parts of speech which are not substantives; they are such entities as qualities or relations” (ibid., 90). Because universals and particulars alike are possible objects of acquaintance both have to be real. However, according to Russell they are real in a different sense. Particulars have existence in time whereas universals have timeless being. The first ones exist, the other subsist. They form two different worlds in that the world of particulars consists of items that are “fleeting, vague, without sharp boundaries” whereas the world of universals “is unchangeable, rigid, exact” (ibid., 100).

This rough outline of Russell’s epistemic universe is meant to emphasize only those aspects of his position that are of relevance for an assessment of idealistic tendencies in his approach to knowledge. As in the case of Moore it is tempting to interpret his commitment to a timeless world of universals as pointing if not to an endorsement at least to a toleration of a position that is difficult to distinguish from some version of an ontological idealism. But again one has to acknowledge that such a verdict is not very significant because one could as well describe this position as a version of ontological realism. It just depends on what is claimed to be the distinctive feature of idealism. If ontological idealism is a position characterized by taking for granted the reality of conceptual entities that are not mind-dependent then both Moore and Russell endorse ontological idealism. If idealism is meant to be a position which takes conceptual items to be mind-dependent then both are realists with respect to concepts. However, it is hard to see how Russell can avoid epistemological idealism given his views about physical objects. This is so because of his sense-datum theory, according to which what is immediately present to us, i.e., what we are acquainted with when we are acquainted with particulars, are just sense-data and not objects in the sense of individual things with qualities standing in relations to each other. For him “among the objects with which we are acquainted are not included physical objects (as opposed to sense-data)” (ibid., 52). Physical objects are constructions we form out of sense-data together with some descriptive devices, and only with respect to these constructions can we have knowledge by description, i.e. propositional knowledge. If epistemological idealism is understood (as has been done here) as involving the claim that what we take to be objects of knowledge are heavily dependent on some activity of the knowing subject, then the very idea of an object as a construction guarantees the endorsement of epistemological idealism. Thus, in contrast to their self-proclaimed revolt against the idealism of Berkeley and Bradley, the positions of both Moore and Russell are by no means free of traits that connect them rather closely to well known currents in modern idealism; and these features, above all the supposition that knowers may be immediately presented with some sorts of informational atoms, whether properties, sense-data, or whatever, but that all further knowledge, or all knowledge beyond immediate acquaintance, involves constructive activities of the mind, are common throughout a great deal of recent philosophy.

To trace the subterranean presence of at least epistemological idealism throughout the remainder of twentieth-century philosophy would exceed the brief for this entry. There is room here for just a few hints of how such an account would go. At Oxford, some influence of idealism continued until World War II in the person of Robin George Collingwood, who was influenced by Hegel and the Italian philosopher Benedetto Croce but was a very original thinker. Collingwood’s most characteristic position might be his claim that metaphysics is the study of the presuppositions of human knowledge, at various historical periods, rather than of independently existing entities; thus he might be considered an epistemological idealist. In Germany, Neo-Kantianism, especially of the Marburg school, from Hermann Cohen to Ernst Cassirer, thus from the 1870s to the 1940s, stressed human conceptualization, in Cassirer’s case in the guise of “symbolic forms,” while trying to steer clear of traditional metaphysical questions; their position might thus also be considered a form of epistemological rather than ontological idealism. Neo-Kantianism in turn influenced the broader stream of analytic philosophy through the person of Rudolf Carnap, whose Logical Construction of the World (1927) analyzes knowledge in terms of relations constructed on perceived similarities in qualities of objects, thus taking a subjectivist starting-point and then adding constructive activities of the mind to it—a form of epistemological idealism. Nelson Goodman’s Structure of Appearance (1951) undertook a similar project. Subsequent to the Logical Construction , Carnap distinguished between questions “internal” to a conceptual framework or system and “external” questions about which conceptual framework to adopt, which can be decided only on pragmatic or even aesthetic grounds, and this too might be considered a form of epistemological idealism. Thomas Kuhn’s famous conception of “paradigms” of science which are not automatically rejected because of refractory evidence but are given up only when an alternative paradigm comes to seem preferable can be seen as being in the Carnapian tradition, as can Hilary Putnam’s “internal realism” of the 1980s, and both these positions thus reflect some of the motives for epistemological idealism. Even W.V. Quine, who was a committed physicalist in the sense of believing that other sciences are in principle reducible to physics, nevertheless reflected the impulse to epistemological idealism in his conception of the “web of belief,” that is, the idea that knowledge consists in a body of beliefs, from particular observation statements down to logical principles, which faces experience only as a whole and which can be modified at any point within it in order to accommodate refractory experience, as seems best. A similar idea was already to be found in Cassirer’s early work Substance and Function (1912), which points to the underlying impulse to epistemological idealism. Wilfrid Sellars’s conception of the “space of reasons”, taken up in Robert Brandom’s inferentialism, also reflects this impulse, although Sellars’s most explicitly Kantian work, Science and Metaphysics (1968), gives what might be regarded as a pragmatist rather than idealist spin to Kant’s phenomena/noumena distinction, interpreting the noumenal as what would be known if science were complete, an idea clearly inspired by Charles Sanders Peirce rather than by Kant—although not completely different in spirit from Royce’s idea that the error of our particular beliefs can be understood only by comparison to a body of complete and completely true beliefs, not to some independent, non-belief reality. These are just a few examples of how some of the most prominent paradigms, to borrow Kuhn’s term, of analytic philosophy still reflect the impulse to epistemological idealism even though the name “idealism” was anathematized by Moore, Russell, and the New Realists.

Analytical philosophy has been overwhelmingly influenced by the paradigm of the natural sciences, and often committed to some form of naturalism; but as the examples of Green and Royce as well as earlier idealists such as Schelling make clear, there is no necessary incompatibility between idealism and some forms of naturalism. In particular, naturalism, especially broadly understood as a methodology rather than ontology, is not automatically committed to the kinds of realism, especially the naïve realism of assuming that our representations reproduce the physical constitution of external objects, that were initially opposed to idealism. One might even get the impression that in contemporary scientifically-oriented philosophy idealism is no longer considered a threat. The way in which in current discussions in the philosophy of mind some idealistic conceptions under the general name of “Panpsychism” are taken seriously (Nagel, Chalmers) seems to be a good indicator of this tendency.

In fact, we might suggest in closing, the main alternative to what is essentially the epistemological idealism of a great deal of twentieth-century philosophy has not been any straightforward form of realism, but rather what might be called the “life philosophy” originally pioneered by Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1916), then extensively developed by Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), and, without Heidegger’s political baggage, by the French philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908–1961). The central idea of this approach to philosophy is that the starting-point of thought and knowledge is neither anything “subjective” like sense-data or ideas nor anything simply objective like the objects of science, but the lived experience of “being-in-the-world”, from which both the “subjective” such as sense-data and the “objective” such as objects theorized by science are abstractions or constructions made for specific purposes, but which should not be reified in any way that creates a problem of getting from one side to the other, let alone any possibility of reducing one side to the other and thus ending up with a choice between idealism and realism. Apart from all issues of style, and whether this has been clear to the two parties or not, perhaps the deepest reason for the on-going divide between “analytical” and “continental” philosophy is the on-going tension between the impulse to epistemological idealism and the attraction of the idea that “being-in-the-world” precedes the very distinction between subjective and objective. But then again, this underlying idea of the Heideggerian approach to philosophy may already be suggested in the work of Schelling, so perhaps the fundamental debate within twentieth-century philosophy has taken place within a framework itself inspired by a form of idealism.

At the beginning of the twenty-first century, however, idealism, understood as a philosophical program, may be sharing the fate of many other projects in the history of modern philosophy. Originally conceived in the middle of the eighteenth century as a real alternative to materialistic and naturalistic perspectives, it may now become sublated and integrated into views about the nature of reality that ignore metaphysical oppositions or epistemological questions connected with the assumption of the priority of mind over matter or the other way round. Instead the focus may be shifting to establishing a “neutral” view according to which “anything goes” (Feyerabend) as long as it does not contradict or at least is not incompatible with our favored metaphysical, epistemological and scientific (both natural and social) methods and practices.

  • Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb (1739). Metaphysics : A Critical Translation with Kant’s Elucidations, Selected Notes, and Related Materials . Translated and edited by Courtney J. Fugate and John Hymers. London: Bloomsbury, 2013.
  • Berkeley, George (1948–1957). The Works of George Berkeley . Edited by A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop. 9 vols. London and Edinburgh: Thomas Nelson and Sons.
  • Bosanquet, Bernard (1885). Knowledge and Reality . London: Kegan Paul, Trench and Trubner.
  • ––– (1888). Logic, or the Morphology of Knowledge . Oxford: Clarendon Press. Second edition, 1911.
  • ––– (1912). The Principle of Individuality and Value . London: Macmillan.
  • ––– (1913). The Value and Destiny of the Individual . London: Macmillan.
  • ––– (1913). The Distinction between Mind and its Objects. Manchester: Sherratt and Hughes.
  • Bradley, Francis Herbert (1876). Ethical Studies . Oxford: Clarendon Press. Second edition, 1927.
  • ––– (1883). The Principles of Logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Second edition, 1922.
  • ––– (1893). Appearance and Reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Second edition, 1897.
  • ––– (1914). Essays on Truth and Reality . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • ––– (1935). Collected Essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Caird, Edward (1879). “Mr. Balfour on Transcendentalism”. Mind 4: 111–115.
  • ––– (1883). Hegel. Edinburgh: William Blackwood.
  • ––– (1889). The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant . 2 vols. Glasgow: James Maclehose.
  • ––– (1892). Essays on Literature and Philosophy. 2 vols. Glasgow: James Maclehose.
  • ––– (1893). The Evolution of Religion . Glasgow: James Maclehose.
  • ––– (1904). The Evolution of Theology in the Greek Philosophers . Glasgow: James Maclehose.
  • Carnap, Rudolf (1928). The Logical Structure of the World . Translated by Rolf George. Second edition. LaSalle: Open Court, 2003.
  • Cassirer, Ernst (1910–21). Substance and Function and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity . Translated by William Curtis Swabey and Marie Collins Swabey. Chicago: Open Court, 1923.
  • ––– (1923–29). The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms . Translated by Ralph Manheim. 3 vols. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1953–59.
  • Collingwood, Robin George (1924). Speculum Mentis, or The Map of Knowledge . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • ––– (1933). An Essay on Philosophical Method . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • ––– (1938). The Principles of Art . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • ––– (1940). An Essay on Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • ––– (1942). The New Leviathan, revised edition. Edited by David Boucher. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992
  • ––– (1945). The Idea of Nature . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (1946). The Idea of History . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Descartes, René (1985–91). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes . Edited by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Feyerabend, Paul (1975). Against Method. Outline of an anarchistic Theory of Knowledge . New York: Humanities Press.
  • Fichte, Johann Gottlieb (1845–46). Johann Gottlieb Fichtes sämmtliche Werke . Edited by Immanuel Hermann Fichte. Berlin: Veit. Cited as [ Werke ], followed by volume and page number.
  • Green, Thomas Hill (1874). Introduction to Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature . Reprinted in his Works , Volume I, pp. 1–371.
  • ––– (1883). Prolegomena to Ethics . Oxford: Clarendon Press. Fifth edition, 1907.
  • ––– (1885–88). Works of Thomas Hill Green . Edited by R.L. Nettleship. 3 vols. London: Longmans, Green.
  • ––– (1886). Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant . Reprinted in Works, Volume II, pp.1–155.
  • Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1801). The Difference between Fichte and Schelling’s System of Philosophy . Translated by H.S. Harris and Walter Cerf. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1977.
  • ––– (1807). Phenomenology of the Spirit . Translated by Arnold V. Miller. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977.
  • ––– (1812). Science of Logic . Translated by George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
  • ––– (1968– ). Gesammelte Werke . Edited by the Rheinisch-Westfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag. Cited as [ GW ], followed by volume and page number.
  • Hobbes, Thomas (1651). Leviathan . Edited by Noel Malcolm. 3 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2012.
  • ––– (1655). De Corpore . In Thomas Hobbes, Body, Man, and Citizen. Edited by Richard S. Peters. New York: Collier Books, 1962.
  • ––– (1640) Elements of Law, Natural and Politic , edited by Ferdinand Toennies (1889), London: Simpkin & Marshall.
  • Hume, David (1739–40). A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by David Fate and Mary J. Norton. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007.
  • ––– (1748). An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding . Edited by Tom L. Beauchamp. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000.
  • Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich (1994). The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel Allwill. Translated by George di Giovanni. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queens University Press.
  • Kant, Immanuel (1781/87). Critique of Pure Reason . Translated by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • ––– (1783ff). Theoretical Philosophy after 1781 . Edited by Henry E. Allison and Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
  • ––– (1900– ). Kants gesammelte Schriften . Edited by the Royal Prussian (later German, then Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy of Sciences. 29 vols. Berlin: Georg Reimer, later Walter de Gruyter.
  • ––– (2005). Notes and Fragments . Edited by Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1969). Philosophical Papers and Letters . Edited by Leroy E. Loemker. Second edition. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Locke, John (1689). An Essay concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.
  • McTaggart, John McTaggart Ellis (1896). Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (1901). Studies in Hegelian Cosmology . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second edition, 1918.
  • ––– (1910). A Commentary on Hegel’s Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (1921–7). The Nature of Existence . 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (1934). Philosophical Studies . Ed. by S.V.Keeling. London. Arnold.
  • Malebranche, Nicolas (1674–75). The Search after Truth . Translated by Thomas M. Lennon and Paul J. Olscamp. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1980.
  • ––– (1688). Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion. Edited by Nicholas Jolley and David Scott. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
  • Moore, George Edward (1899). “The Nature of Judgment”. Mind new series 8: 176–93.
  • ––– (1922). Philosophical Studies . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • ––– (1959). Philosophical Papers. London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Nietzsche, Friedrich (1882). The Gay Science . Edited by Bernard Williams, translated by Josefine Nauckhoff. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
  • ––– (1887). On the Genealogy of Morality. Edited by Keith Ansell-Perason, translated by Carol Diethe. Second edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
  • ––– (1980). Sämtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Bänden . Edited by Giorgio Colli & Mazzino Montinari. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. Cited as [ KSA ], followed by the volume number, a colon, and the fragment number(s).
  • Royce, Josiah (1885). The Religious Aspect of Philosophy: A Critique of the Bases of Conduct and Faith . Boston: Houghton, Mifflin & Co.
  • ––– (1892). The Spirit of Modern Philosophy: An Essay in the Form of Lectures. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.
  • ––– (1899–1901). The World and the Individual, First and Second Series. 2 vols. New York: MacMillan.
  • ––– (1918). The Problem of Christianity . New York: MacMillan.
  • ––– (1919). Lectures on Modern Idealism . New Haven: Yale University Press
  • Russell, Bertrand (1912). The Problems of Philosophy . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974.
  • Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph (1797). Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature . Translated by Errol E. Harris and Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Cited as [ IP ]
  • ––– (1800). System of Transcendental Idealism . Translated by Peter Heath. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1978.
  • ––– (1856–61). Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling’s Sämmtliche Werke . Edited by Karl F.A. Schelling. I Abtheilung Vols. 1–10, II Abtheilung Vols. 1–4. Stuttgart: Cotta. Cited as [ SW ], followed by volume and page number.
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur (1819). The World as Will and Representation. Translated by Judith Norman, Alaistair Welchman, and Christopher Janaway. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Cited as [ WWR ].
  • Spinoza, Baruch (1677). Ethics . In The Collected Works of Spinoza, Volume I , edited and translated by Edwin Curley. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985. Or Spinoza: Complete Works . Translations by Samuel Shirley, edited by Michael L. Morgan. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.
  • Wolff, Christian (1751). Vernünftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt, und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt. Neue Auflage hin und wieder vermehret. Halle: Renger.
  • Allison, Henry E. (1983). Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense. New Haven Yale University Press. Second edition, 2004.
  • Altmann, Matthew C., editor (2014). The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Ameriks, Karl (2000). Kant and the Fate of Autonomy: Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (2012). Kant’s Elliptical Path. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Ameriks, Karl, editor (2000). The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1976). ‘”The Question of Linguistic Idealism”. Acta Fennica Philosophica 28: 188–215. Reprinted in her Collected Papers, Volume I: From Parmenides to Wittgenstein . Oxford: Blackwell, 1981. Pp.112–33.
  • Barrett, Clifford (1932). Contemporary Idealism in America. New York: Macmillan.
  • Baugh, Bruce (2003). The French Hegel: From Surrealism to Postmodernism . London: Routledge.
  • Beiser, Frederick C. (1987). The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (2002). German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism, 1791–1801 . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (2013). Late German Idealism: Trendelenberg and Lotze. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Blanshard, Brand (1939). The Nature of Though, 2 vols. London: George Allen & Unwin.
  • Boyle, Nicholas, Liz Dizley, and Karl Ameriks, editors (2013). The Impact of Idealism . 4 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. See especially Volume I: Philosophy and Natural Sciences.
  • Brandom, Robert B. (2000). Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (2002). Tales of the Mighty Dead: Historical Essays in the Metaphysics of Intentionality. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (2009). Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Breazeale, Daniel (2013). Thinking Through the Wissenschaftslehre: Themes from Fichte’s Early Philosophy . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bubner, Rüdiger (2003). The Innovations of Idealism . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Butler, Judith (1987). Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in Twentieth-Century France. New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Campbell, Charles Arthur (1931). Scepticism and Construction: Bradley’s Sceptical Principle as the Basis of Constructive Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • ––– (1938). “In Defence of Free-Will”. Glasgow inaugural lecture, reprinted in his In Defence of Free-Will, with Other Essays. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1967.
  • ––– (1956). “Self-Activity and its Modes”. In H.D.Lewis, editor. Contemporary British Philosophy: Personal Statements , Third Series. London: Macmillan. Pp.85–115.
  • Chalmers, David (1996). The Conscious Mind . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Cunningham, G. Watts (1933). The Idealistic Argument in Recent British and American Philosophy . New York: Century.
  • Davidson, Donald (1984). “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme”. In Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation . Oxford; Oxford University Press. Pp. 183–98.
  • Dicker, George (2011). Berkeley’s Idealism: A Critical Examination . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Dudley, Will (2007). Understanding German Idealism. London: Acumen.
  • Dunham, Jeremy, Iain Hamilton Grant, and Sean Watson (2011). Idealism: The History of a Philosophy . London: Acumen.
  • Ewing, Alfred Cyril (1934). Idealism: a Critical Survey. London: Methuen.
  • ––– (1957). The Idealist Tradition: From Berkeley to Blanshard. Glencoe: The Free Press.
  • Findlay, John N. (1970). Ascent to the Absolute . London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Fogelin, Robert J. (1985). Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Hume Nature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Foster, John (1982). The Case for Idealism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Förster, Eckart (2013). The Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy: a Systematic Reconstruction . Translated by Brady Bowman. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Garber, Daniel, and Beatrice Longuenesse, editors (2008). Kant and the Early Moderns . Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Gardner, Sebastian and Paul Franks (2002). “From Kant to Post-Kantian German Idealism”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , supplementary volume, 76: 211–46.
  • Griffin, Nicholas (1991). Russell’s Idealist Apprenticeship . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Guyer, Paul (1987). Kant and the Claims of Knowledge . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hammer, Espen, editor (2007). German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives. London and New York: Routledge.
  • Franks, Paul (2005). All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments, and Skepticism in German Idealism . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Henrich, Dieter (2003). Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Horstmann, Rolf-Peter (1984). Ontologie und Relationen: Hegel, Bradley, Russell und die Kontroverse über interne und externe Beziehungen . Königstein: Athenäum.
  • ––– (1991). Die Grenzen der Vernunft: Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen und Motiven des Deutschen Idealismus. Frankfurt: Athenäum.
  • Hylton, Peter (1990). Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2013). “Idealism and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy”. In Boyle, Nicholas, et. al., editors, The Impact of Idealism . Vol. 1, pp. 323–46.
  • Jaeschke, Walter and Andreas Arndt (2012). Die Klassischer Deutsche Philosophie nach Kant: System der reinen Vernunft und ihre Kritik 1785–1845 . Munich: C.H. Beck.
  • Kemp Smith, Norman (1924). Prolegomena to an Idealist Theory of Knowledge . London: Macmillan.
  • ––– (1941). The Philosophy of David Hume: A Critical Study of its Origins and Central Doctrines. London: Macmillan.
  • Köhnke, Klaus Christian (1991). The Rise of Neo-Kantianism . Translated by R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Kuklick, Bruce (1977). The Rise of American Philosophy: Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1860–1930. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • ––– (1985). Churchmen and Philosophers: From Jonathan Edwards to John Dewey. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Kutschera, Franz v. (2006). Die Wege des Idealismus . Paderborn: Mentis.
  • Longuenesse, Béatrice (2007). Hegel’s Critique of Metaphysics. Translated by Nicole J. Simek. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • McDowell, John (2009). Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel and Sellars. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Mander, W.J. (1997). “McTaggart’s Argument for Idealism”. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 11: 53–72.
  • ––– (2011). British Idealism: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Martin, Wayne (1997). Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte’s Jena Project. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
  • Moore, Adrian W. (1997). Points of View . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Moore, Adrian W. (2012). The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Moyar, Dean, editor (2010). The Routledge Companion to Nineteenth Century Philosophy. London: Routledge.
  • Muirhead, J. H. (1931). The Platonic Tradition in Anglo-Saxon Philosophy: Studies in the History of Idealism in England and America . London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Myers, Gustavus (1925). The History of American Idealism . New York: Boni and Liveright.
  • Nauern, F.-G. (1971). Revolution, Idealism, and Human Freedom: Schelling, Hölderlin, and Hegel and the Crisis of Early German Idealism. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Nicholson, Peter P. (1990). The Political Philosophy of the British Idealists . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • O’Hear, Anthony, editor (1999). German Philosophy Since Kant . Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 44. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Pinkard, Terry (1994). Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (2002). German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Pippin, Robert B. (1989). Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (1997). Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations , CUP
  • Quinton, Anthony (1971). “Absolute Idealism”. Proceedings of the British Academy 57: 303–29.
  • Redding, Paul (2009). Continental Idealism: Leibniz to Nietzsche . London: Routledge.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (1973). Conceptual Idealism. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • ––– (1987). Ethical Idealism. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
  • ––– (1991). Human Knowledge in Idealistic Perspective . Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • ––– (2005). Reason and Reality: Realism and Idealism in Pragmatic Perspective . Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Rogers, Dorothy (2005). America’s First Women Philosophers: Transplanting Hegel 1860–1925. London: Continuum.
  • Rosen, Gideon (1994). “Objectivity and Modern Idealism: What is the question?” In Michaelis Michael & John O’Leary-Hawthorne, editors. Philosophy in Mind . Dordrecht: Kluwer. Pp.277–319.
  • Sandkühler, Hans Jörg, editor (2005). Handbuch deutscher Idealismus. Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.
  • Sassen, Brigitte, editor (2000). Kant’s Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sellars, Wilfrid (1963). Science, Perception, and Reality . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • ––– (1968). Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • ––– (1997). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Edited by Robert B. Brandom. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Sprigge, T.L.S. (1983). The Vindication of Absolute Idealism . Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
  • ––– (2006). The God of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2011). The Importance of Subjectivity: Selected Essays in Metaphysics and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stern, Robert (1990). Hegel, Kant and the Structure of the Object. London: Routledge.
  • ––– (2002) Hegel and the ‘Phenomenology of Spirit.’ London: Routledge. Second edition, 2013.
  • ––– (2009). Hegelian Metaphysics . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stroud, Barry (1977). Hume . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Thomas, James (1999). Intuition and Reality: A Study of the Attributes of Substance in the Absolute Idealism of Spinoza . Dartmouth: Ashgate.
  • Willmann, Otto (1894–97). Geschichte des Idealismus . Vols. 1–3. Braunschweig: F. Vieweg.
  • Wood, Allen W (1990). Hegel’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Idealism , edited bibliography at PhilPapers
  • German Idealism , Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Idealism , The Basics of Philosophy

Bayle, Pierre | Berkeley, George | Bradley, Francis Herbert | Cambridge Platonists | -->Carnap, Rudolf --> | Cassirer, Ernst | Cohen, Hermann | Collingwood, Robin George | Descartes, René | Dilthey, Wilhelm | dualism | egoism | Epicurus | epistemology | Feyerabend, Paul | Fichte, Johann Gottlieb | Green, Thomas Hill | Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich | Heidegger, Martin | Hobbes, Thomas | Hume, David | Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich | James, William | Kant, Immanuel | Kuhn, Thomas | Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm | Locke, John | Malebranche, Nicolas | McTaggart, John M. E. | Merleau-Ponty, Maurice | monism | Moore, George Edward | naturalism | Nietzsche, Friedrich | occasionalism | -->ontology --> | Peirce, Charles Sanders | physicalism | Plato | rationalism vs. empiricism | realism | Reinhold, Karl Leonhard | Royce, Josiah | Russell, Bertrand | Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von | Schopenhauer, Arthur | self-consciousness | Sellars, Wilfrid | skepticism | Spinoza, Baruch | Wolff, Christian

Acknowledgments

The authors owe thanks to a group that met in Berlin in July, 2014, to discuss a draft of this entry, including Dina Emundts, Eckart Förster, Gunnar Hindrichs, Charles Larmore, Paul Redding, Robert Stern, and Tobias Rosefeldt; we owe special thanks to Larmore for his numerous and detailed comments on that draft and to Stern for his generous assistance with the bibliography. We also owe thanks to Justin Broackes for his participation in the seminar we gave at Brown University in Spring and Fall 2013 where we also discussed much of this material.

Copyright © 2015 by Paul Guyer < paul_guyer @ brown . edu > Rolf-Peter Horstmann < rolf . horstmann @ rz . hu-berlin . de >

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

Stanford Center for the Study of Language and Information

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2016 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology

1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology

Philosophy, One Thousand Words at a Time

Idealism Pt. 1: Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism

Author: Addison Ellis Category: Historical Philosophy , Metaphysics , Epistemology Word Count: 1000

Editor’s Note: This essay is the first of two essays in a series authored by Addison on the topic of philosophical idealism. Part 2 on Kant’s Transcendental Idealism can be read here .

We often take it for granted that we have some knowledge about the way reality is. For instance, it seems clear to me that I know there is a computer screen directly in front of my face, and I believe it is clearly true that I know how to get to the refrigerator from where I currently sit. But what is the nature of the computer screen and the refrigerator? Common sense tells us that they are bundles of physical stuff and that our minds have become adapted, perhaps through a process like evolution, to knowing about and acting with respect to them.

Idealism, on the contrary, is the view that what reality is like depends upon the way the mind works. There are many distinct versions of idealism in the history of philosophy, and we will consider three of the most important versions over three distinct installments: Berkeley’s subjective idealism, Kant’s transcendental idealism, and Hegel’s absolute idealism. This, then, will be part one of a three-part installment on idealism, and we will start with George Berkeley’s subjective idealism.

Berkeley

1. Two Arguments for Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism

George Berkeley, an 18 th -Century Irish philosopher, held that esse est percipi , or “to be is to be perceived.” When I perceive a black dog, according to many philosophers in the early modern period, I am in possession of a representational state – that is, my mind is affected by a physical thing, the dog, which in turn causes my mind to generate a mental representation of the dog. What I perceive, then, is really only a representation, from which I infer the existence of the thing represented. This is called indirect realism.

Berkeley challenged this traditional picture in the following way. 1 First, when we take a representation to accurately represent an object in the world, we do so on the assumption that the representation resembles the object in some way. But, Berkeley argues, we are in no position to say that our ideas resemble anything other than other ideas. According to Berkeley, we cannot compare ideas with material objects since to have knowledge of a material object would require that we know it via some idea. Thus, all we ever encounter are ideas themselves, and never anything material.

If Berkeley is right, then we never have knowledge of anything material whatsoever; we only ever know our own ideas. This is part of a larger attack in which Berkeley argues that we are not entitled to believe that matter exists, in which case the only things that do exist include minds, ideas, and God. Berkeley is putting forth a view that is sometimes called subjective idealism : subjective, because he claims that the only things that can be said to exist are ideas when they are perceived. Thus, my black dog exists only when I am currently in possession of the idea of my black dog. If I leave my dog behind when I walk to the store, she no longer exists, and so her existence is purely dependent upon a subject’s perception of her.

In addition to the resemblance argument above, and to strengthen his attack on realism and materialism, Berkeley also argues that matter is impossible.

The basic idea goes like this: Matter is defined as physical stuff which can exist independently of our minds. We ordinarily take matter to be the stuff that makes up reality, and this stuff is supposed to go on existing whether we are perceiving it or not. That is, we think of matter as stuff that can exist unconceived. But we can never conceive of matter except through some idea. If so, then we cannot conceive of matter as something unconceived. In fact, it would be absurd to say so, since necessarily in conceiving of matter, we are conceiving of an idea , and surely we cannot conceive of an idea that is unconceived. If all of this is true, then, Berkeley argues, matter as it is defined is impossible . 2 If matter is impossible, then no material objects exist, and it is only possible for minds, ideas, and God to exist.

2. Problems with Subjective Idealism

If Berkeley is right, and things exist only insofar as they are ideas being perceived by a mind, then there were never physical objects like mountains and animals before minds capable of knowledge (i.e., minds like ours) came into existence. Since things, for Berkeley, exist only insofar as they are being perceived (esse est percipi), and since no minds were perceiving anything millions of years ago, then nothing would have existed millions of years ago, if Berkeley is right. This is an unsettling thought, since it directly conflicts with both common sense and our best scientific worldview.

However, Berkeley may be able to avoid such a problem by suggesting that our ideas continue to exist in the mind of God even when we cease to possess them ourselves. When we have ideas, especially perceptual ones, they seem to be passive with respect to our minds. That is, in perception we seem to have little choice in what ideas we encounter. Because ideas are passive, they do not cause themselves. Additionally, since ideas are always possessed by a mind, and since our minds do not seem to simply produce their own ideas (since we passively receive them), they must be given to us from another mind. For this reason, Berkeley believes (i) that God exists, and (ii) that our ideas have their origin in the mind of God. If this is true, then arguably my dog does not simply pop out of existence when I cease to perceive her, since all our ideas are ultimately held in the mind of God. 3

3. Conclusions

We should take away three important points from this essay. First, idealism is the view that the way reality is depends upon the way the mind is. Second, one version of idealism, Berkeleyan subjective idealism, holds that all there is are ideas, the minds that possess those ideas, and God. 4 Third and finally, while Berkeley’s view is not without its problems, his arguments are compelling and worth taking very seriously.

1  Berkeley rejects both indirect and direct realism, to be more precise. In traditional philosophical parlance, it is common to define realism as the view that there exists a mind-independent reality. If this is what realism means, then no idealist is a realist. Curiously, as we will see with Kant’s transcendental idealism, a distinction can be made between what Kant calls transcendental realism and empirical realism. Kant believes that he can be an empirical realist and a transcendental idealist .

2  See Dialogue Two in the  Three Dialogues of Hylas and Philonous.

3  This is by no means the end of the discussion. As we will see in the next installment, Kant has more objections to Berkeley’s subjective idealism.

4  God is a kind of spirit or mind, but one that is infinite rather than finite like us.

Berkeley, George.  Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous . Indianapolis: Hackett 1979.

Downing, Lisa. “George Berkeley.”  Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Stanford University, 10 Sept. 2004. Web. 07 July 2014. <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/berkeley/>.

Related Essays

The Mind-Body Problem: What Are Minds? by Jacob Berger

About the Author

Addison Ellis is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at The American University in Cairo. His interests include Kant and Post-Kantian European Philosophy, with special attention to the topics of self-consciousness, ontology, and cognitive capacities and attitudes. philpeople.org/profiles/addison-ellis

Follow 1000-Word Philosophy on Facebook and Twitter and subscribe to receive email notifications of new essays at 1000WordPhilosophy.com

Share this:.

Comments are closed.

What is Materialism? History and Concepts

  • First Online: 05 October 2021

Cite this chapter

materialism vs idealism essay

  • Javier Pérez-Jara 12 , 13 ,
  • Gustavo E. Romero 14 , 15 &
  • Lino Camprubí 16  

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 447))

636 Accesses

2 Citations

1 Altmetric

Despite the central presence of materialism in the history of philosophy, there is no universal consensus on the meaning of the word “matter” nor of the doctrine of philosophical materialism. Dictionaries of philosophy often identify this philosophy with its most reductionist and even eliminative versions, in line with Robert Boyle’s seventeenth century coinage of the term. But when we take the concept back in time to Greek philosophers and forward onto our own times, we recognize more inclusive forms of materialism as well as complex interplays with non-materialist thought about the place of matter in reality, including Christian philosophy and German idealism. We define philosophical materialism in its most general way both positively (the identification of reality with matter understood as changeability and plurality) and negatively (the negation of disembodied living beings and hypostatized ideas). This inclusive approach to philosophical materialism offers a new light to illuminate a critical history of the concept of matter and materialism from Ancient Greece to the present that is also attentive to scientific developments. By following the most important connections and discontinuities among theoretical frameworks on the idea of matter, we present a general thread that offers a rich and plural, but highly cohesive, field of investigation. Finally, we propose building on rich non-reductionist materialist philosophies, such as Mario Bunge’s systemic materialism and Gustavo Bueno’s discontinuous materialism, to elaborate powerful theoretical alternatives to both physicalism and spiritualism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

materialism vs idealism essay

A Matter of Faith: Derrida, Žižek, and the Fourth ‘Overcoming of Gnosis’

materialism vs idealism essay

Materialism without Materialism: Slavoj Žižek and the Disappearance of Matter

materialism vs idealism essay

Some of these philosophers, as we are going to see, used the language of traditional myth to talk about abstract philosophical conceptions; that is, they used that language as a set of rhetorical devices, along with giving traditional concepts (such as “cosmos”) a new philosophical meaning. Only a minority of them still held literal beliefs in traditional mythological elements (such as reincarnation). For that reason, although the new way of thinking that they created emerged from a specific sociocultural context (rather than appearing ex nihilo ), it had enough new and revolutionary features to be considered and classified apart.

Although Hesiod started his Theogony with an impersonal chaos (a prefiguration of later metaphysical notions), he also offered anthropomorphic explanations for the rest of natural phenomena.

According to some scholars, such as Jennifer Peck, Heraclitus’ notions of logos and God, although very similar, should not be identified, since Heraclitus’ logos is the pattern present in all things, whereas God refers to the principle of unity of opposites. It is undeniable that Heraclitus’ fragments are obscure, and often difficult to interpret; but what seems clear is that for him, the notions of God and logos , if not identical, are very similar and refer to the universal impersonal mechanism and structure of reality.

This philosopher introduced an important critique of Parmenides’ view of reality as a (Euclidean) giant sphere: since a sphere necessarily implies an outer space, reality has to be infinite .

For a full account of the atomists, with fragments, doxography and commentaries see Taylor ( 1999 ).

It is important to note that Plato talked about the Demiurge using the explicit language of myth. Since in several Dialogues Plato used other myths as allegorical teachings rather than literalist dogmas, it is also possible that his myth of the Demiurge has a non-literalist anthropomorphic reading. But while in other Platonic myths the allegorical reading is clear, in his myth of the Demiurge it is not. For that reason, it is more than likely that Plato, as Anaxagoras and Socrates before, held a real belief in some kind of personal mind that gave form to the world.

Aristotle also considered the existence of lesser “gods” who, along with the main God, move the planets, but they do so in a completely impersonal and blind way.

Although Epicurus considered Greek mythology’s gods as human fictions, he recommended his disciples to visit Greek temples and contemplate the serenity of the gods’ statues. Such activity could have psychological and ethical benefits.

The case of the relationships between Stoicism and Christianity is very interesting. Several Stoic ideas related to ethics and politics were accepted and transformed by some Christian thinkers, at the same time that they rejected Stoic metaphysics.

This is Docetism’s theological doctrine, according to which the body of Jesus was an illusion. But, despite its partial influence in other Christian communities, Docetism was soon perceived as a dangerous heresy by more powerful and popular forms of Christianity: see Wahlde ( 2015 ), Freeman ( 2011 ), and Papandrea ( 2016 ).

Through these binary oppositions between the sins generated by matter, and the virtues generated by the spirit, St. Paul did not seem no notice the theological contradiction that it was not matter, but the pure spirit of Satan who introduced evil in reality, before the creation of matter.

Even though Plato drew from the Orphic despise of matter, he did not plea for asceticism and mortification of the flesh. On the contrary, Plato encouraged good nutrition, bodily aesthetics, and sports.

Here, we use the concept of “neophobia” in Bunge’s critical sense, i.e as the metaphysical approach that denies ontological novelty in reality: “The most popular idea about novelty is that whatever appears to be new actually existed previously in a latent form: that all things and all facts are ’pregnant’ with whatever may arise from them. An early example of such neophobia is the conception of causes as containing their effects, as expressed by the scholastic formula ’There is nothing in the effect that had not been in the cause’.” (Bunge 2010 , p. 87).

According to which everything is connected with everything else through God (Bueno 1972 ).

Aquinas even defended that matter could be eternal, despite been created by God. Only by Revelation do we know that the material universe had a beginning in time: see Aquinas ( 1948 ) and Gilson ( 1960 ).

Sharing similar theological problems and concerns, these combination between negative and positive theologies also took place in medieval Judaism and Islam: see Kars ( 2019 ) and Fagenblat ( 2017 ), respectively.

The recovery of God’s anthropomorphic attributes was achieved through cataphatic theology, which sought to understand God in positive terms, emphasizing the divine attributes that we can find through the Revelation.

Hume’s (and, later, Stuart Mill’s) psychologism is different in that it can be considered an even softer version of this hypostatization of the psyche. Both authors downplay the organic and operational side of human existence, along with reducing abstract concepts, ideas and relations to psychological processes. But the independence of the mind respect of the nervous system is not held; it just suggested as a possibility.

Kant’s pure categories of the understanding are: unity, plurality, and totality for the concept of quantity; reality, negation, and limitation, for the concept of quality; inherence and subsistence, cause and effect, and community for the concept of relation; and possibility–impossibility, existence–nonexistence, and necessity and contingency, for the concept of mode (see Kant 2008 [1787]; Heidegger 1997 [1929]; and Strawson 2018 ).

It is well-known that Kant ( 2015 [1788]) introduced this God again in the Critique of Practical Reason as a postulate for moral action. But this does not contradict that, from an epistemological point of view, Kant held that the Christian God was just an idea.

Russell ( 1972 [1945]), p. 718.

Russell ( 1972 [1945]), p. 718. Russell also contended that “Modern philosophy begins with Descartes, whose fundamental certainty is the existence of himself and his thoughts, from which the external world is to be inferred. This was only the first stage in a development, through Berkeley and Kant, to Fichte, for whom everything is only an emanation of the ego. This was insanity, and, from this extreme, philosophy has been attempting, ever since, to escape into the world of every-day common sense.” Russell ( 1972 [1945]), p. XXI.

Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre was later reworked by Fichte in various versions. The most well-known version of the work was published in 1804, but other versions appeared posthumously.

That is, for Fichte, absolute reality cannot be (as Schelling will defend later) both subjective and objective.

The concept of Tathandlung reminds of Husserl’s Leistung . But Husserl’s transcendental idealism did not deny the Kantian “thing in it self” as Fichte did; it just placed it between brackets: see Pérez-Jara 2014 .

This book was published thanks to Kant’s support. As such, it was briefly mistaken by the public to be a fourth Kantian Critique. This confusion granted Fichte a considerable philosophical fame.

Important to note is that Schelling’s lectures on positive philosophy were attended by personalities such as Engels, Bakunin, Kierkegaard, and Humboldt.

The World as Will and Representation ’s first edition was published in late 1818, with the date 1819 on the title–page. In 1844, a second edition appeared. This edition was divided into two volumes: the first one was an edited version of the 1818 edition, while the second volume was a collection of commentaries about the ideas expounded in the first volume. In 1859, at the end of Schopenhauer’s life, a third expanded edition was published.

Schopenhauer’s metaphysics of sexuality brilliantly anticipates many hypotheses of evolutionary biology: see Pérez-Jara ( 2011 ).

Schopenhauer agreed with Schulze’s critique of Kant’s contradictory use of causality. For Schopenhauer, the thing in it self (i.e., the Will) is not the cause of our sensations. Rather, our sensations are a (non-causal) manifestation of the Will.

Here, we use the concept of organoleptic in its usual meaning of relative to our sensory experiences, so the “organoleptic world” is the set of phenomena, from the taste of wine to the colors of the sky, filtered through our sense organs.

For a very interesting philosophical analysis on this topic, see: Bueno ( 1972 ), pp. 50, 52, 60, 72, 283, 288.

Jarochewski ( 1975 ), p. 168.

Bunge ( 2010 ), p. 127.

Notable exceptions can be found in the work of J.C.C. Smart, Graham Nerlich, and Hugh Price who worked extensively on the ontology of spacetime and related problems.

On the other hand, Bunge ( 2010 ) opposed both approaches, because for him there cannot be states or events without entities. Romero, however, points out that materialist ontologies based on concrete things or particular events are formally equivalent (Romero 2013 , 2016 ): to consider things or events as basic is rather a matter or taste and not of fact.

Bunge ( 2010 ), p. 148.

It would also be interesting to wonder if these philosophers, in their daily lives (or even in their lectures and conferences) exclusively use complex neuroscientific terminology each time that they want to express that they feel tired, forgot something, feel disappointed, or are hungry.

Also, see in this volume his chapter and his discussion with Javier Pérez-Jara.

While Bueno himself referred to his system as “philosophical materialism” in the 1970s, as he was seeking to differentiate it from historical materialism, that conceptualization is too general and common to other philosophies; in later works, Bueno spoke of “discontinuous materialism”.

Abulafia, D. 2008. The Discovery of Mankind. Atlantic Encounters in the Age of Colombus . New Haven: Yale University Press.

Google Scholar  

Aikin, J.M.T., and W. Johnston. 1808. General Biography , vol. 7. London: St. Paul Church Yard.

Aquinas, Th. 1948. The Summa Theologica . New York: RCL Benziger.

Ansey, P.R. 2017. Newton and Locke. In The Oxford Handbook of Newton , eds. Schliesser, E., and C. Smeenk. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Aristotle. 2016. Metaphysics . Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

Armstrong, D.M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Armstrong, D.M. 1997. A World of States of Affair . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

Ashworth, W.B. 1990. Natural history and the emblematic world view. In eds. D. Lindberg and R. Westman Reappraisals of the Scientific Revolution . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Avicebron (Solomon ibn Gabirol). 2014. The Font of Life ( Fons vitae ). Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.

Barnes, J. 1982. The Presocratic Philosophers . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Barrera-Osorio, A. 2007. Experiencing nature: The Spanish American Empire and the Early Scientific Revolution . Austin: University of Texas Press.

Bauer, B. 1841. Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte der Synoptiker . Leipzig: Wigand.

Bauer, W. 1971. Orthodoxy and Heresy in Earliest Christianity . Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

Beiser, F. 2014. After Hegel. German Philosophy 1840–1900 . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Bickle, J. 1992. Revisionary physicalism. Biology and Philosophy 7(4): 411–430.

Article   Google Scholar  

Blenkinsopp, J. 2011. Creation, Un-Creation, Re-Creation: A Discursive Commentary on Genesis , 1–11. London: T&T Clarke International.

Borges, J.L. 1989[1952]. Nueva refutación del tiempo. In: Otras Inquisiciones . In: Obras Completas . Buenos Aires: Emecé, 1989. Vol. 2, p. 146.

Bourke, V.J. 2019. Augustine’s Quest of Wisdom: The Life and Philosophy of the Bishop of Hippo . Providence: Cluny Media LLC.

Bowman, C., and Y. Estes (eds.). 2016. J. G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798–1800) . New York: Routledge.

Broda, E. 1983. Ludwig Boltzmann . Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.

Bryant, L. 2014. Correlationism. In The Meillassoux Dictionary , eds. Gratton, P. and P.J. Ennis. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Brakke, D. 2012. The Gnostics: Myth, Ritual, and Diversity in Early Christianity . Harvard: Harvard University Press.

Bruno, G.A. (ed.). 2020. Schelling’s Philosophy: Freedom, Nature, and Systematicity . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Büchner, L. 1904[1855]. Kraft und Stoff oder Grundzüge der natürlichen Weltordnung , 21st ed. Leipzig: Theodore Thomas.

Bueno, G. 1972. Ensayos Materialistas . Madrid: Taurus.

Bueno, G. 1974. La Metafísica Presocrática . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Bueno, G. 1981. Introducción a la Monadología . In Leibniz, Monadología . Oviedo: Pentalfa, p. 11–47.

Bueno, G. 1989. La teoría de la esfera y el descubrimiento de América. El Basilisco 1: 3–32.

Bueno, G. 1990a. Ganzes/Teil. Holismus. Materie. Naturwissenchaften. Europäische Enzyklopädie zu Philosophie und Wissenschaften . Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

Bueno, G. 1990b. Materia . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Bueno, G. 1992-1993. Teoría del cierre categorial , vol 5. Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Bueno, G. 1996. El Sentido de la Vida. Seis Lecturas de Filosofía Moral . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Bueno, G. 2007. La Fe del Ateo . Madrid: Temas de Hoy.

Bueno, G. 2008. La vuelta del revés de Marx. El Catoblepas 76. http://nodulo.org/ec/2008/n076p02.htm .

Bueno, G. 2012. . Nankin: Nanking University.

Bueno, G. 2016. El Ego Trascendental . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Bueno, G. 2019. The Happiness Delusion. Debunking the Myth of Happiness . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Bunge, M. 2003. Emergence and Convergence : Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge . Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Bunge, M. 2006. Chasing Reality: Strife over Realism . Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Bunge, M. 2009[1959]. Causality and Modern Science: Fourth Revised Edition . New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

Bunge, M. 2010. Matter and Mind: A Philosophical Inquiry . New York: Springer.

Camprubí, L. 2009. Traveling around the Empire: Iberian voyages, the sphere, and the Atlantic origins of the Scientific Revolution. Eä,Revista de Humanidades Médicas & Estudios Sociales de la Ciencia y la Tecnología 1(2): 1–19.

Carabine, D. 2015. The Unknown God : Negative Theology in the Platonic Tradition : Plato to Eriugena . Eugene: Wipf and Stock.

Carnap, R. 1959[1932/1933]. Psychology in physical language. In Logical Positivism , ed. A.J. Ayer. New York: The Free Press.

Cañizares-Esguerra, J. 2006. Nature, Empire and Nation : Explorations of the History of Science in the Iberian World . Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Cao, T.Y. 1997. Conceptual Development of 20th Century Field Theories . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Chemla, K. 2012. The History of Mathematical Proof in Ancient Traditions . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Childe, V.G. 2009[1958]. The Prehistory of European Society . London: Spokesman Press.

Childe, V.G. 2017[1951]. Social Evolution . Delhi: Aakar Books.

Churchland, P.S. 1981. Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 78(2): 67–90.

Churchland, P.S. 1986. Neurophilosophy : Toward a Unified Science of the Mind / Brain . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Churchland, P.S., and T.J. Sejnowski. 1993. The Computational Brain . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Churchland, P.M. 1984. Matter and Consciousness : A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Chryssavgis, J. 2008. In the Heart of the Desert : The Spirituality of the Desert Fathers and Mothers . Bloomington: World Wisdom.

Clark, S. 1997. Thinking with Demons : The Idea of Witchcraft in Early Modern Europe . Oxford: Clarendon.

Coakley, J.W., and A. Sterk (eds.). 2004. Readings in World Christian History . New York: Orbis Books.

Coole, D., and S. Frost (eds.). (2010). New Materialisms : Ontology, Agency, and Politics . Durham: Duke University Press Books.

Copleston, F. 1993[1955]. A History of Philosophy, Vol. 1 : Greece and Rome From the Pre-Socratics to Plotinus . New York: Image.

Coxon, A.H. 2009. The Fragments of Parmenides : A Critical Text with Introduction . Athens: Parmenides Publishing.

Critchley, S. 2019. Tragedy, the Greeks, and Us . New York: Pantheon.

Crombie, A.C. 1953. Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science, 1100–1700 . Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Daston, L. 1991. Marvelous Facts and Miraculous Evidence in Early Modern Europe. Critical Inquiry 18(1): 93–124.

Daston, L. and Park, K. 1998. Wonders and the Order of Nature. 1150–1750 . New York: Zone Books.

Davies, S. 2016. Renaissance Etnography and the Invention of the Human. New Worlds, Maps and Monsters . Cambridge. Cambridge University Press.

Day, J. 2002. Yahweh and the Gods and Goddesses of Canaan . Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press.

Day, J. 2015. From Creation to Babel : Studies in Genesis 1–11 . Edinburgh: Bloomsbury T&T Clark.

Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained . Boston: Little, Brown.

Díaz Díaz, G. 2003. Hombres y Documentos de la Filosofía Española : S-Z : Vol. VII . Madrid: Consejo Superior De Investigaciones Científicas.

Dionysius the Areopagite. 2004. On the Divine Names and the Mystical Theology , trans. C. E. Rolt. Lake Worth: Nicolas Hays.

Dupré, J. 1993. The Disorder of Things : Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Dunn, G. D. 2004. Tertullian . New York: Routledge.

Engels, F. 2012[1883]. Dialectics of Nature . London: Wellred.

Fagenblat, M. Ed. 2017. Negative Theology as Jewish Modernity . Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Feingold, M. Ed. 2003. Jesuit Science and the Republic of Letters . Cambridge: The MIT Press.

Fichte, J. G. 1982[1794]. The Science of Knowledge : With the First and Second Introductions . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fichte, J.G. 2000[1797]. Foundations of Natural Right . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fichte, J.G. 2009[1868]. The Science of Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Library.

Fichte, J.G. 2010[1792]. Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Frauenstädt, J. 1856. Der Materialismus. Seine Wahrheit und sein Irrthum. Eine Erwiderung auf Dr. L. Büchner’s “Kraft und Stoff” , Leipzig: Brockhaus.

Freeman, C. 2011. A New History of Early Christianity . New Haven: Yale University Press.

Gabriel, M. 2017. I am Not a Brain : Philosophy of Mind for the 21t Century . Cambridge: Polity.

Gabriel, M. 2015. Why the World Does Not Exist . Cambridge: Polity.

García Valverde, J.M., P. Maxwell-Stuart, 2019. Gomez Pereira’s Antoniana Margarita. A Work on Natural Philosophy,Medicine and Theology . Leiden: Brill.

Geest, P.V. 2011. The Incomprehensibility of God : Augustine as a Negative Theologian . Leuven: Peeters Publishers.

Gilson, E.H. 1960. The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine . New York: Random House.

Goetschel, W. 2004. Spinoza’s Modernity : Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine . Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press.

Gómez Pereira, A. 2000 [1554]. Antoniana Margarita . Santiago de Compostela: USC-Fundación Gustavo Bueno.

Grafton, A. 1992. New Worlds, Ancient Texts : The Power of Tradition and the Shock of Discovery . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Grafton, A., and G. Siraisi (eds.). 2000. Natural Particulars : Nature and the Disciplines in Renaissance Europe . Cambridge: The Mit Press.

Graham, D.W. 2006. Explaining the Cosmos . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Graham, D.W. 2010. The Texts of the Early Greek Philosophy , Part I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Graham, D.W. 2013. Science before Socrates . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Grant, E. 2001. God and Reason in the Middle Ages . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gregory, F. 1977. Scientific Materialism in Nineteenth Century Germany . Dordrecht: Reidel.

Gutas, D. 2014. Orientations of Avicenna’s Philosophy : Essays on his Life, Method, Heritage . New York: Routledge.

Haaparanta, L., and Koskinen, H.J. (eds.). 2012. Categories of Being : Essays on Metaphysics and Logic . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Harman, G. 2010. I am also of the opinion that materialism must be destroyed. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 28(5): 772–790.

Harman, G. 2016. Immaterialism : Objects and Social Theory . Cambridge: Polity.

Harman, G. 2009. Prince of Networks : Bruno Latour and Metaphysics . Melbourne: Re.press

Harman, G. 2011. The Quadruple Object . United Kingdom: Zero Books.

Harris, M. 1979. Cultural Materialism : The Struggle for a Science of Culture . New York: Random House.

Harrison, P. 2015. The Territories of Science and Religion . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Hegel, G.W.F. 1977[1807]. Phenomenology of Spirit . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hegel, G.W.F. 1991[1820]. Elements of the Philosophy of Right . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hegel, G.W.F. 2015a[1817]. Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hegel, G.W.F. 2015b[1816]. The Science of Logic . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Heidegger, M. 1997[1929]. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics . Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Hempel, C. 1949[1980]. The logical analysis of psychology. In Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology , ed. N. Block, Vol. 1, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Henry, J. 2008. The Scientific Revolution and the Origins of Modern Science , 3rd edn. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Hesse, M.B. 2005. Forces and Fields . New York: Dover.

Hevia Echeverría, J. 2007. La concordia de Molina, en Luis de Molina, Concordia del libre arbitrio [1588]. Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Hidalgo, A., and S.G. Bueno 1982. I Congreso de Teoría y Metodología de las Ciencias . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Hume, D. 2000[1739]. A Treatise of Human Nature . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Insua, P. 2018. El orbe a sus pies: Magallanes y Elcano: cuando la cosmografía española midió el mundo . Madrid: Ariel.

Innocent III (Lotario Dei Segni). 1977. De Miseria Condicionis Humane . Georgia: University of Georgia Press.

Jacob, M. 2019. The Secular Enlightenment . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Jacobi, F.H. 1799. Jacobi an Fichte . Hamburg: Perthes.

Jaeger, W. 2003[1936]. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers . Eugene: Wipf and Stock.

James, C.L.R. 1980[1948]. Notes on Dialectics : Hegel, Marx, Lenin . London: Allison & Busby.

Jarochewski, M. 1975. Psychologie im 20. Jahrhundert . Berlin: Volk und Wissen.

Johnston, W.M. 2013. Encyclopedia of Monasticism . New York: Routledge.

Josephson-Storm, J. 2017. The Myth of Disenchantment : Magic,Modernity,and the Birth of the Human Sciences . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Kahn, C.H. 1994. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology . Cambridge : Indianapolis Hackett Publishing.

Kant, I. 1998[1793]. Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kant, I. 2007[1790]. Critique of Judgment . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kant, I. 2008[1787]. Critique of Pure Reason . London: Penguin Classics.

Kant, I. 2015[1788]. Critique of Practical Reason . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kars, A. 2019. Unsaying God : Negative Theology in Medieval Islam . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kirk, G.S., J. Raven, and M. Schofield. 1983. The Presocratic Philosophers . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kirsch, J. 2005. God Against the Gods : The History of the War Between Monotheism and Polytheism . London: Penguin Books.

Klein, J. 2008. Francis Bacon’s Scientia Operativa, the tradition of the workshops, and the secrets of Nature. In Philosophies of Technology. Francis Bacon and His Contemporaries , eds. C. Zittel, G. Engel, R. Nanni, and N.C. Karafyllis Leiden: Brill, p.21–49.

Kojevnikov, A. 2004. Stalin’s Great Science : The Times and Adventures of Soviet Physicists . London: Imperial College Press.

Lange, F. 1866. Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegnwart . Iserlohn: J. Baedeker.

Latour, B. 2005. Reassembling the Social : An Introduction to Actor – Network – Theory . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lenin, V.I. 2011[1909]. Materialism and Empirio-Criticism : Critical Comments on A Reactionary Philosophy . Whitefish: Literary Licensing, LLC.

Lesher, J.H. 1992. Xenophanes of Colophon : Fragments : A Text and Translation with Commentary . Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Lindberg, D.C. 2007. The Beginnings of Western Science , Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Long, A.A. 1974. Hellenistic Philosophy : Stoics, Epicureans and Skeptics . London: Duckworth.

Long, A.A., and D.N. Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Long, A.A. (ed.) 1999. The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophers . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Loraux, N. 2002. The Mourning Voice : An Essay on Greek Tragedy . Cornell: Cornell University Press.

MacCulloch, D. 2010. Christianity : The First Three Thousand Years . London: Penguin.

MacMullen, R. 1984. Christianizing the Roman Empire : A . D. 100–400 . New Haven: Yale University Press.

Martino, A.A. (ed.) 2019. El Último Ilustrado. Libro de Homenaje al Centenario del Nacimiento de Mario A. Bunge . Buenos Aires: Eudeba.

Marx, K. 1975[1841], in: Collected Works of Karl Marx and Frederick Engels : Volume 1 . New York: International Publishers.

Marx, K. 2014[1844]. Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right . Seattle: Amazon.

Marx, K., and F. Engels. 1976. Collected Works of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,1845–47, Vol. 5 : Theses on Feuerbach,The German Ideology and Related Manuscripts . New York: International Publishers Co.

Matthews, M.R. (ed.) 2019. Ed. Mario Bunge : A Centenary Festscrhift . Cham: Springer.

May, G. 2004. Creatio Ex Hihilo . London: Continuum International.

McClendon, J.H.III. 2004. C . L . R. James’s Notes on Dialectics : Left Hegelianism or Marxism-Leninism ? Washington: Lexington Books.

McKirahan, R.D. 1994. Philosophy before Socrates . Cambridge: Indianapolis Hackett Publishing Co.

Meillassoux, Q. 2009. After Finitude : An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency . London: Continuum.

Meli D.B. 2006. Thinking with Objects. The Transformation of Mechanics in the Seventeenth Century . Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

Nicholson, D.J., and J. Dupré. 2018. Everything Flows : Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Nebe, G. 2002. Creation in Paul’s theology. In Creation in Jewish and Christian Tradition , eds. Y. Hoffman, H.G. Reventlow. Sheffield: Sheffield Academic Press.

Nestle, W. 1975[1940]. Vom Mythos zum Logos ; Die Selbstenfaltung Des Griechischen Denkens . Stuttgart: Alfred Kroner Verlag.

Netz, R. 1999. The Shaping of Deduciton in Greek Mathematics. A Study in Cognitive History . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Neurath, O. 1983[1931]. Physicalism: The philosophy of the vienna circle. In Philosophical Papers 1913 – 1946 , eds. R.S. Cohen, M. Neurath. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

Newman, W. 2006. Atoms and Alchemy. Chysmistry and the Experimental Origins of the Scientific Revolution . Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

North, J. 1994. The Fontana History of Astronomy and Cosmology . Fontana Press.

Ongay, I. 2019. Mente y materia: una revisión de la filosofía de la mente de Mario Bunge. In El Último Ilustrado. Homenaje al Centenario del Nacimiento de Mario A. Bunge , ed. Antonio Martino. Buenos Aires: Eudeba.

O’Rourke, Fran. 2016. Pseudo-Dionysius and the Metaphysics of Aquinas . Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

Padgen, A. 1982. The Fall of Natural Man : The American Indian and the Origins of Comparative Ethnology . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Papandrea, J.L. 2016. The Earliest Christologies : Five Images of Christ in the Postapostolic Age . Downers Grove: IVP Academic.

Pardo J. 2002. Oviedo, Monardes, Hernández: El Tesoro Natural de América, Colonialismo y Ciencia en el Siglo XVI . Madrid: Nivola.

Pasternack, L. 2013. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason . New York: Routledge.

Peña, V. 1974. El Materialismo de Spinoza. Ensayo sobre la Ontología Spinozista . Madrid: Revista de Occidente.

Pereira, G. 2019[1554]. Antoniana Margarita : A Work on Natural Philosophy, Medicine and Theology . Leiden: Brill Academic Pub.

Pérez-Jara, J. 2011. La importancia del cuerpo como “constitutivo formal” de todo viviente en la filosofía de Schopenhauer. Thémata. Revista de filosofía : 424–438.

Pérez-Jara, J. 2014. La Filosofía de Bertrand Russell . Oviedo: Pentalfa.

Peeters, E., L.V. Molle, and K. Wils (eds.). 2011. Beyond Pleasure : Cultures of Modern Asceticism . New York: Berghahn Books.

Pimentel, J. 2001. The Iberian vision: Science and empire in the framework of a Universal monarchy, 1500–1800. In Nature and Empire : Science and the Colonial Enterprise, Osiris Special Issue,15 , ed. R. MacLeod, p. 17–30.

Place, U.T. 1956. Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology 47: 44–50.

Portuondo, M. 2009. Secret Science. Spanish Cosmography and the New World . Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Primero, G., and S. y Barrera. 2019. El concepto de materia en los sistemas filosóficos de Gustavo Bueno y Mario Bunge. Scientia in Verba 3: 34–52.

Purrington, R.D. 1997. Physics in the Nineteenth Century . New Jersey: Rugters University Press.

Ramsey, W., S. Stich, and J. Garon. 1990. Connectionism, eliminativism and the future of folk psychology. Philosophical Perspectives 4: 499–533

Randall, J.H. 1958. The Role of Knowledge in Western Religion . Boston: Starr King Press

Robinson, Th.A., and H.P. Rodrigues. 2014. World Religions : A Guide to the Essentials . Ada: Baker Academic.

Rocca, G.P. 2008. Speaking the Incomprehensible God : Thomas Aquinas on the Interplay of Positive and Negative Theology . Washington: The Catholic University of America Press.

Rogers, A.J. 1978. Locke’s Essay and Newton’s Principia . Journal for the History of Ideas 39(2): 217–232.

Romero, G.E. 2012. Parmenides reloaded. Foundations of Science 17: 291–299.

Romero, G.E. 2013. From change to spacetime: An eleatic journey. Foundations of Science 18: 139–148.

Romero, G.E. 2016. A formal ontological theory based on timeless events. Philosophia 44: 607–622.

Romero, G.E. 2018. Scientific Philosophy . Cham: Springer.

Rorem, P. 1993. Pseudo-Dionysius : A Commentary on the Texts and an Introduction to Their Influence . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Rorty, R. 1970. In defense of eliminative materialism. The Review of Metaphysics XXIV.

Rosental, M., and P. Yudin. 1945[1940]. Diccionario de Filosofía . Santiago de Chile: Nueva América.

Russell, B. 1972[1945]. A History of Western Philosophy . New York: Touchstone.

Schelling, F.W.J. 2012[1842]. Historical-Critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mythology . Albany: SUNY Press.

Schelling, F.W.J. 2009[1804]. Philosophy and Religion . Ashland: Spring Publications.

Schopenhauer, A. 2014[1859]. The World as Will and Representation,Vol. I . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Schopenhauer, A. 2016[1851]. Parerga and Paralipomena : Short Philosophical Essays, Vol. I . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Schopenhauer, A. 2017[1851]. Parerga and Paralipomena : Short Philosophical Essays,Vol. II . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Schopenhauer, A. 2018[1859]. The World as Will and Representation, Vol. II . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J.R. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Searle, J.R. 1995. The Construction of Reality . New York: The Free Press.

Searle, J.R. 1997. The Mystery of Consciousness . New York: New York Review.

Searle, J.R. 2005. Mind : A Brief Introduction . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Searle, J.R. 2007. Freedom & Neurobiology . New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

Sellars, R.W. 1969[1922]. Evolutionary Naturalism . New York: Russell & Russell.

Sellars, R.W. 1970. Principles of Emergent Realism . St. Louis: Warren H Green.

Shapin, S., and S. Schaffer. 1985. Leviathan and the Air-Pump,Hobbes,Boyle,and the Experimental Life . New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

Sheehan, Th. 2014. Making Sense of Heidegger : A Paradigm Shift . Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

Slaveva-Griffin, S., and P. Remes. 2017. The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism . New York: Routledge.

Smart, J.C.C. 1963. Philosophy and Scientific Realism . New York: The Humanities Press.

Smith, P.H. 2004. The Body of the Artisan : Art and Experience in the Scientific Revolution . Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Smith, C., and M.N. Wise. 1989. Energy and Empire: A Biographical Study of Lord Kelvin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Strauss, D.F. 1835. Das Leben Jesu, kritisch bearbeitet . Tübingen: C. F. Osiander.

Strawson, P. 2018. The Bounds of Sense : An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason . New York: Routledge.

Taylor, C.C.W. 1999. The Atomists : Leucippus and Democritus . Toronto: The University of Toronto Press.

Thomson, A. 2014. French eighteenth-century materialists and natural law. History of European Ideas 42(2): 1–13.

Van Melsen, A.G. 2004. From Atomos to Atom . New York: Dover.

Vermeir, K. 2011. Wonder, magic, and natural philosophy. The disenchantment thesis revisited in eds. M. Deckard and P. Losonczi Philosophy Begins in Wonder . Eugene: Wipf and Stock, p. 43–71.

Vogt, C. 1855. Kühlerglaube und Wissenschaft: Eine Streitschrift gegen Hofrath Wagner in Göttingen . Gießen: Ricker.

von Wahlde, U.C. 2015. Gnosticism, Docetism,and the Judaisms of the First Century : The Search for the Wider Context of the Johannine Literature and Why It Matters . London: T&T Clark.

Wallis, R.T. 1995. Neoplatonism . Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

Weber, M. 1946[1918]. Science as vocation. In From Max Weber : Essays in Sociology , eds. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Free Press.

Weeks, A. 1997. Paracelsus. Speculative Theory and the Crisis of the Early Reformation . Albany: State University of New York.

Weidemann, H.U. (ed.). 2013. Asceticism and Exegesis in Early Christianity : Reception and Use of New Testament Texts in Ancient Christian Ascetic Discourses . Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

Westfall, R.S. 1983. Never At Rest : A Biography of Isaac Newton . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

White, L.A. 2007[1959]. The Evolution of Culture . New York: Routledge.

Wise, M.N. 2018. Aesthetics, Industry and Science. Hermann von Helmholtz and the Berlin Physical Society. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Wooton, D. 2015. The Invention of Science : A New History of the Scientific Revolution . London: Penguin.

Young, F. 1991. ‘Creatio Ex Nihilo’: A context for the emergence of the Christian doctrine of Creation. Scottish Journal of Theology 44: 139–152.

Yourgrau, W., A. van der Merwe, and G. Raw. 1982. Treatise on Irreversible and Statistical Thermophysics . New York: Dover.

Zizek, S. 2013. Less Than Nothing: Hegel and the Shadow of Dialectical Materialism . New York: Verso Books.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Beijing Foreign Studies University, Beijing, China

Javier Pérez-Jara

Yale University, New Haven, CT, USA

Instituto Argentino de Radioastronomía (IAR) (CONICET; CICPBA; UNLP), Villa Elisa, Buenos Aires, Argentina

Gustavo E. Romero

Facultad de Ciencias Astronómicas y Geofísicas, Universidad Nacional de La Plata, La Plata, Provincia de Buenos Aires, Argentina

Departamento de Lógica y Filosofía de la Ciencia, University of Seville, Sevilla, Spain

Lino Camprubí

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

International Business School, Beijing Foreign Studies University, Beijing, China

Departamento de Lógica y Filosofía de la Ciencia, Universidad de Sevilla, Sevilla, Spain

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Pérez-Jara, J., Romero, G.E., Camprubí, L. (2022). What is Materialism? History and Concepts. In: Romero, G.E., Pérez-Jara, J., Camprubí, L. (eds) Contemporary Materialism: Its Ontology and Epistemology. Synthese Library, vol 447. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-89488-7_1

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-89488-7_1

Published : 05 October 2021

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-030-89487-0

Online ISBN : 978-3-030-89488-7

eBook Packages : Religion and Philosophy Philosophy and Religion (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

IMAGES

  1. Theories of Materialism and Idealism

    materialism vs idealism essay

  2. (DOC) Marxism and the Modern World (Idealism vs. Materialism)

    materialism vs idealism essay

  3. Idealism and Materialism in Karl Marx's Writings

    materialism vs idealism essay

  4. Comparison between Materialism and Idealism

    materialism vs idealism essay

  5. Marx: idealism vs. materialism

    materialism vs idealism essay

  6. Idealism vs. Materialism: What’s the Difference?

    materialism vs idealism essay

VIDEO

  1. Materialism vs Dualism Question

  2. Realism vs Idealism

  3. Internal and External Relations

  4. Idealism, Materialism and Solipsism

  5. Communists Don't Fear the Future

  6. Realism and Idealism in International Relations || Theories in IR || By Muhammad Akram

COMMENTS

  1. What is the difference between idealism and materialism?

    It's hard to give a once-and-for-all answer to this question, because what exactly materialism and idealism amount to depends largely on the historical era you have in mind. That said, here's one way to cash out these notions. Materialism is the view that material objects exist. Idealism is the view that every object either is, or depends for ...

  2. Materialism Vs. Idealism: A Comparative Study

    Materialism and Idealism are two fundamental concepts in philosophy that have influenced our understanding of the world for centuries. Materialism posits that everything in the universe is made up of matter, while Idealism suggests that reality is a mental construct.

  3. Idealism vs. Materialism

    Learn how idealism and materialism are two contrasting philosophical perspectives that explain the nature of reality. Compare their attributes, characteristics, and foundations, and see how they differ and overlap in various aspects.

  4. Idealism

    Already in The Epistle to the Reader of An Essay concerning Human Understanding (1690) ... In Berkeley's view, the only alternative to idealism is not materialism but skepticism. Up until the point at which he introduces the mind of God into his argument, all of Berkeley's epistemological considerations might be thought of as expressions of ...

  5. Materialism vs. Idealism: Is the World What You Think?

    Explore the contrasting views on the nature of reality, from ancient to modern perspectives. Learn the key principles, theories, applications, and criticisms of materialism and idealism in science, ethics, metaphysics, and more.

  6. Difference between Materialism and Idealism

    Learn the difference between materialism and idealism, two philosophical views that have shaped the history of thought and society. Materialism emphasizes the physical world and human agency, while idealism focuses on the spiritual world and supernatural forces.

  7. Materialism in Literature & Literary Theory

    Learn how materialism, a philosophical stance that prioritizes physical matter, influences various literary theories and works. Explore the meanings, arguments, and examples of materialism in relation to Marxism, cultural materialism, eco-criticism, and more.

  8. A Look at Materialism and Idealism as Illustrated by Marx in Comunist

    Marx effectively dismantles idealism and the concept of ideas as the motor of history. After explaining how Hegelians and other idealists view ideas in history (one must separate the ideas of those ruling for empirical reasons, under empirical conditions and as empirical individuals, from these actual rulers, and thus recognize the rule of ideas or illusions in history), Marx spends the rest ...

  9. Idealism

    Idealism is a philosophical view that stresses the role of the ideal or the spiritual in the interpretation of experience. It may assert the ideality of reality, the coherence of truth, the dialectical method, and the centrality of mind in knowledge and being.

  10. The Significance and Shortcomings of Karl Marx

    In this essay I explain both why Karl Marx remains an important thinker and why he is in some respects inadequate. I focus on the central issue of 'materialism vs. idealism,' and briefly explore ways in which contemporary intellectuals still haven't assimilated the insights of historical materialism. In the last section of the paper I examine the greatest weakness of Marxism, its theory of ...

  11. Philosophy Essay Sample: Materialism vs Idealism

    Materialism vs Idealism Samples / Philosophy / Materialism Vs Idealism To get a clear picture of what materialism and idealism means, we can put a basic scenario in our everyday life, example the word "bed" we at once perceive a four legged structure with a mattress and beddings and through that perception, an image is created in our brain.

  12. (PDF) What is Materialism? What is Idealism

    New materialism is not a clear-cut set of theses, or a firmly unified school of thought. It crosses discourses and theoretical commitments, but, as its name indicates, seems consistently to oppose 'new' materialism to an older form, or perhaps several older forms of this doctrine.

  13. Theories of Materialism and Idealism

    Materialism and idealism are two theories that greatly differ but are essentially straightforward to grasp in terms of contrasting and comparing the two. Karl Marx, a nineteenth century German philosopher and socialist saw materialism as a theory in regards to all reality being based on matter.

  14. Materialism

    Materialism is the view that all facts are causally dependent on or reducible to physical processes. Learn about the different types of materialism, such as mechanical, physicalist, emergent, and dialectical, and their historical origins and implications.

  15. An outline of philosophy. 2. Materialism versus idealism

    We see that materialism and idealism are the two main tendencies in the field of philosophy, but there are other viewpoints also, combinations of ideas and methods that occupy a position between these extremes. For example, agnostics, who cannot decide whether an external reality actually exists apart from ourselves and whether it is possible ...

  16. Idealism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy/Fall 2017 Edition)

    Wolff, often considered the most dedicated Leibnizian of his time (although in fact his position was more eclectic than at least some versions of Leibniz's) set out to integrate the terms "idealism" and "materialism" into his taxonomy of philosophical attitudes of those "who strive towards the knowledge and philosophy of things ...

  17. Idealism Pt. 1: Berkeley's Subjective Idealism

    Esse est percipi means "to be is to be perceived" and is the core of Berkeley's idealism. He argues that only ideas exist and that matter is impossible, but faces problems with explaining the origin and continuity of ideas.

  18. Materialism

    Materialism is a view that matter is the fundamental substance in nature, and that all things, including mental states and consciousness, are results of material interactions. Learn about the history, types, and criticisms of materialism, and how it contrasts with idealism and dualism.

  19. What is Materialism? History and Concepts

    In this chapter we aim at critically and constructively outlining the evolution of philosophical materialism in the Western tradition. This enables us to propose what we consider to be a broader concept of materialism than the one that is today often employed, and thus to provide a rigorous historical framework to the discussion of the subsequent chapters.

  20. Idealism vs Materialism : r/askphilosophy

    The concept of the Anthropocene has definitely made this a much larger conversation lately with marxism and idealism giving way to emergence theories, realisms, and object oriented ontology that tries to de-centre human understandings and knowledge altogether which I think is kind of beautiful.I would also look into new-materialism, and ...

  21. 5 Mentalism, Idealism, and Immaterialism

    A chapter from a book on mental reality that explores the views of Descartes and Berkeley on the nature of mind and matter. It discusses the coherence and distinctiveness of idealism and immaterialism as alternatives to materialism and dualism.

  22. Difference between materialism and idealism : r/askphilosophy

    Materialism is thus more associated with older views on nature (things like ancient atomism, Empedocles' elements and Descartes' extended substance). Idealism can vary significantly, but perhaps one of the general characteristics one could attribute is a rejection of a mind-independent world.

  23. Idealism Vs Materialism

    In the debate between idealism and materialism, the ultimate question is, mind over matter or matter over mind? Materialism and Idealism are the two contrary doctrines in philosophy. According to the materialistic view, the world is entirely mind-independent, composed only of physical objects and physical interactions.